Results for 'Q Science (General)'

134 found
Order:
  1.  60
    Semantic holism and methodological constraints in the study of religion.Mark Q. Gardiner - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 79 (3):281-299.
    The methodology implicit in empirically grounded social scientific studies of religion naturally allies with forms of semantic holism. However, a well known argument which questions whether holism in general is consistent with the fact that languages are learnable can be extended into an epistemological one which questions whether holism is consistent with an empirical methodology. In other words, there is question whether holism, in fact, makes social science possible. I diagnose the assumptions on which that objection rests, pointing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Social, Cognitive, and Neural Constraints on Subjectivity and Agency: Implications for Dissociative Identity Disorder.Peter Q. Deeley - 2003 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 10 (2):161-167.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 10.2 (2003) 161-167 [Access article in PDF] Social, Cognitive, and Neural Constraints on Subjectivity and Agency:Implications for Dissociative Identity Disorder Peter Q. Deeley In this commentary, I consider Matthew's argument after making some general observations about dissociative identity disorder (DID). In contrast to Matthew's statement that "cases of DID, although not science fiction, are extraordinary" (p. 148), I believe that there are natural (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  91
    Conscience, Law, and the Obligation to Obey.Mulford Q. Sibley - 1970 - The Monist 54 (4):556-586.
    The civil rights, antiwar, and student upheavals of our day have served, aside from their primary objectives, to reawaken our consciousness of the basic problems of ethical and political obligation.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  8
    Periodic law, chemical elements and scientific discoveries: considerations from Norwood Hanson and Thomas Kuhn.Cristina Spolti Lorenzetti, Anabel Cardoso Raicik & Luiz O. Q. Peduzzi - 2024 - Foundations of Chemistry 26 (3):447-465.
    The theme surrounding scientific discoveries is quite neglected in and about the sciences, especially in terms of historical and epistemological understanding. Discoveries are often treated as simple information about dates, places, and people. This work presents discussions centered on historical episodes related to chemical elements and the Periodic Law, based on reflections by Thomas Kuhn and Norwood Hanson, aiming to highlight and contextualize specific scientific discoveries' conceptual and epistemological structure. With that in mind, issues related to the inseparability of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  94
    Delegation, subdivision, and modularity: How rich is conceptual structure?Damián Justo, Julien Dutant, Benoît Hardy-Vallée, David Nicolas & Benjamin Q. Sylvand - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (6):683-684.
    Contra Jackendoff, we argue that within the parallel architecture framework, the generality of language does not require a rich conceptual structure. To show this, we put forward a delegation model of specialization. We find Jackendoff's alternative, the subdivision model, insufficiently supported. In particular, the computational consequences of his representational notion of modularity need to be clarified.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  17
    Roundtable: Q&A discussion.Artemy Magun, Kate Khan, Lina Bulakhova, Anastasia Merzenina, Artem Serebryakov & Oleg Aronson - 2022 - Studies in East European Thought 74 (4):605-615.
    This is the Q&A portion of the roundtable that focuses on the crucial issues of individual and collective guilt of the intellectual class in the face of war. The participants address the stratification of Russian society, possibilities and obstacles of dissent, and the eschatological tendencies of history by engaging with each other’s claims and ideas and seeking answers to direct questions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Philosophy of science: classic debates, standard problems, future prospects.John Worrall - 2002 - In Peter K. Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 18-36.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Background Why is Science Special from the Epistemic Point of View? Accumulation in Science, Despite “Revolutions”? Other Issues.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Evidence: philosophy of science meets medicine.John Worrall - 2010 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (2):356-362.
    Obviously medicine should be evidence-based. The issues lie in the details: what exactly counts as evidence? Do certain kinds of evidence carry more weight than others? (And if so why?) And how exactly should medicine be based on evidence? When it comes to these details, the evidence-based medicine (EBM) movement has got itself into a mess – or so it will be argued. In order to start to resolve this mess, we need to go 'back to basics'; and that means (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  9.  1
    (1 other version)Models in science.Edward N. Zalta - 2012 - In Ed Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  18
    (2 other versions)Aristotelian powers: without them, what would modern science do?Nancy Cartwright & John Pemberton - 2013 - In John Greco & Ruth Groff (eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge. pp. 93-112.
    The volume brings together for the first time original essays by leading philosophers working on powers in relation to metaphysics, philosophy of natural and social science, philosophy of mind and action, epistemology, ethics and social and political philosophy. In each area, the concern is to show how a commitment to real causal powers affects discussion at the level in question. In metaphysics, for example, realism about powers is now recognized as providing an alternative to orthodox accounts of causation, modality, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  11.  59
    Philosophy of science: classic debates, standard problems, future prospects.John Worrall - 2002 - In Peter K. Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 18-36.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Background Why is Science Special from the Epistemic Point of View? Accumulation in Science, Despite “Revolutions”? Other Issues.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  57
    Minding the Gap: Epistemology & Philosophy of Science in the Two Traditions.Christopher Norris - 2000 - Univ of Massachusetts Press.
    In this sweeping volume, Christopher Norris challenges the view that there is no room for productive engagement between mainstream analytic philosophers and thinkers in the post-Kantian continental line of descent. On the contrary, he argues, this view is simply the product of a limiting perspective that accompanied the rise of logical positivism. Norris reveals the various shared concerns that have often been obscured by parochial interests or the desire to stake out separate philosophical territory. He examines the problems that emerged (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  13. Aristotelian powers: without them, what would modern science do?Nancy Cartwright & John Pemberton - 2013 - In John Greco & Ruth Groff (eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge. pp. 93-112.
    The volume brings together for the first time original essays by leading philosophers working on powers in relation to metaphysics, philosophy of natural and social science, philosophy of mind and action, epistemology, ethics and social and political philosophy. In each area, the concern is to show how a commitment to real causal powers affects discussion at the level in question. In metaphysics, for example, realism about powers is now recognized as providing an alternative to orthodox accounts of causation, modality, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  14.  14
    Aristotelian powers: without them, what would modern science do?John Greco & Ruth Groff - 2013 - In John Greco & Ruth Groff (eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge. pp. 93-112.
    The volume brings together for the first time original essays by leading philosophers working on powers in relation to metaphysics, philosophy of natural and social science, philosophy of mind and action, epistemology, ethics and social and political philosophy. In each area, the concern is to show how a commitment to real causal powers affects discussion at the level in question. In metaphysics, for example, realism about powers is now recognized as providing an alternative to orthodox accounts of causation, modality, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  5
    (1 other version)Against the completability of science.Nancy Cartwright - 2000 - In Martin William Francis Stone & Jonathan Wolff (eds.), Proper Ambition of Science. New York: Routledge. pp. 209-222.
  16.  6
    Philosophy of science: classic debates, standard problems, future prospects.Peter Machamer & Michael Silberstein - 2002 - In Peter K. Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 18-36.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  15
    Invitation to generalized empirical method: in philosophy and science.Terrance J. Quinn - 2016 - New Jersey: World Scientific.
    Bernard Lonergan identified the need and possibility of what he called "generalized empirical method" in science and philosophy. Implementation will be a future community achievement. The book enters into details of a selection of examples in the sciences and philosophy of science. These are provided not to engage in, or blend the present aim with traditional philosophical debate, but as points of entry to help reveal the possibility and need of balanced empirical method. Taking words of Lonergan: "(Q)uestions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  1
    Against the completability of science.Jonathan Wolff & Martin Stone - 2000 - In Martin William Francis Stone & Jonathan Wolff (eds.), Proper Ambition of Science. New York: Routledge. pp. 209-222.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  59
    Against the completability of science.Nancy Cartwright - 2000 - In Martin William Francis Stone & Jonathan Wolff (eds.), Proper Ambition of Science. New York: Routledge. pp. 209-222.
  20.  26
    Heisenberg’s Umdeutung: a case for a (quantum-)dialogue between history and philosophy of science.Adrian Wüthrich - 2016 - In Raphael Scholl & Tilman Sauer (eds.), The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Springer.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  2
    Book review: ubiquity: the science of history... or why the world is simpler than we think. [REVIEW]Roman Frigg - 2002 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (4):585-591.
    Review of Mark Buchanan, Ubiquity. The Science of History... Or Why The World is Simpler Than We Think, London: Weidenfeld & Nichols, 2000. ISBN 297–64376–2.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  9
    Heisenberg’s Umdeutung: a case for a (quantum-)dialogue between history and philosophy of science.Tilman Sauer & Raphael Scholl - 2016 - In Raphael Scholl & Tilman Sauer (eds.), The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Springer.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  5
    (1 other version)Aristotelian powers: without them, what would modern science do?John Greco & Ruth Groff - 2013 - In John Greco & Ruth Groff (eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge. pp. 93-112.
    The volume brings together for the first time original essays by leading philosophers working on powers in relation to metaphysics, philosophy of natural and social science, philosophy of mind and action, epistemology, ethics and social and political philosophy. In each area, the concern is to show how a commitment to real causal powers affects discussion at the level in question. In metaphysics, for example, realism about powers is now recognized as providing an alternative to orthodox accounts of causation, modality, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  24.  2
    Models in science.Edward N. Zalta - 2012 - In Ed Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    Q fever as an anthropological prism for revealing how farmers live with microbes.Émilie Ramillien, Patrice Cayre, Xavier Fourt, Élodie Rousset & Elsa Jourdain - forthcoming - Agriculture and Human Values:1-17.
    To develop effective public health management strategies, it is necessary to account for the viewpoints of all stakeholders. Thus, anthropological approaches can potentially inform strategies for preventing and managing zoonotic diseases. Here, we use Q fever as a starting point for exploring how small ruminant farmers perceive the reality of microbes by disentangling the farmers’ often subtle relationships with their livestock, disease, and the world in general. We found that livestock farmers feel like they exist in the borderlands between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Book review: a companionable coverage of the philosophy of science[REVIEW]Roman Frigg - 2009 - Metascience 18 (1):139-142.
    Review of Stathis Psillos and Martin Curd (eds), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, London: Routledge, 2008. Pp. xxvii + 619.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  30
    By-Person Factor Analysis in Clinical Ethical Decision Making: Q Methodology in End-of-Life Care Decisions.William Wong, Arnold R. Eiser, Robert G. Mrtek & Paul S. Heckerling - 2004 - American Journal of Bioethics 4 (3):W8-W22.
    Objective: To determine the usefulness of Q methodology to locate and describe shared subjective influences on clinical decision making among participant physicians using hypothetical cases containing common ethical issues. Design: Qualitative study using by-person factor analysis of subjective Q sort data matrix. Setting: University medical center. Participants: Convenience sample of internal medicine attending physicians and house staff (n = 35) at one midwestern academic health sciences center. Interventions: Presented with four hypothetical cases involving urgent decision making near the end of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Connected knowledge: science, philosophy, and education.Alan H. Cromer - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    When physicist Alan Sokal recently submitted an article to the postmodernist journal Social Text, the periodical's editors were happy to publish it--for here was a respected scientist offering support for the journal's view that science is a subjective, socially constructed discipline. But as Sokal himself soon revealed in Lingua Franca magazine, the essay was a spectacular hoax--filled with scientific gibberish anyone with a basic knowledge of physics should have caught--and the academic world suddenly awoke to the vast gap that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  29. The Scientist qua Policy Advisor Makes Value Judgments.Katie Siobhan Steele - 2012 - Philosophy of Science 79 (5):893-904.
    Richard Rudner famously argues that the communication of scientific advice to policy makers involves ethical value judgments. His argument has, however, been rightly criticized. This article revives Rudner’s conclusion, by strengthening both his lines of argument: we generalize his initial assumption regarding the form in which scientists must communicate their results and complete his ‘backup’ argument by appealing to the difference between private and public decisions. Our conclusion that science advisors must, for deep-seated pragmatic reasons, make value judgments is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  30.  40
    Aquinas’s Definition of Good: Ethical-Theoretical Notes On De Veritate, Q. 21.Ronald Duska - 1974 - The Monist 58 (1):151 - 162.
    It is a rather remarkable fact that in most discussions of Aquinas’s ethics, Q. 21 of the De Veritate which deals with Aquinas’s notion of Good, is almost entirely overlooked. For example D. J. O’Connor’s book Aquinas and Natural Law refers only once to the De Veritate and that is not a reference to Q. 21. Even the massive work of Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, in the entire third section which deals with Aquinas’s moral theory has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Review. Explorations in economic methodology: From Lakatos to empirical philosophy of science. R Backhouse. [REVIEW]Richard Bradley - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (2):316-318.
  32. Defusing Bertrand’s Paradox.Zalán Gyenis & Miklós Rédei - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (2):349-373.
    The classical interpretation of probability together with the principle of indifference is formulated in terms of probability measure spaces in which the probability is given by the Haar measure. A notion called labelling invariance is defined in the category of Haar probability spaces; it is shown that labelling invariance is violated, and Bertrand’s paradox is interpreted as the proof of violation of labelling invariance. It is shown that Bangu’s attempt to block the emergence of Bertrand’s paradox by requiring the re-labelling (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33. An inferential conception of scientific representation.Mauricio Suárez - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):767-779.
    This paper defends an inferential conception of scientific representation. It approaches the notion of representation in a deflationary spirit, and minimally characterizes the concept as it appears in science by means of two necessary conditions: its essential directionality and its capacity to allow surrogate reasoning and inference. The conception is defended by showing that it successfully meets the objections that make its competitors, such as isomorphism and similarity, untenable. In addition the inferential conception captures the objectivity of the cognitive (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   254 citations  
  34.  7
    If P, Then Q. [REVIEW]Jesús M. Marroquin - 1993 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 8 (1):191-192.
    Este libro pertenece a la colección “The problems of Philosophy. Their past and present”, cuyo editor general es Ted Honderich. Como ya el título de la colección indica, lo que se pretende en cada volumen es recoger un problema importante, dentro de la filosofía, y presentar alguna nueva contribución. Cada libro se divide en dos partes. En la primera se hace una exposición histórica del problema y en la segunda el autor realiza su contribución. Con respecto a la configuración (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  91
    Otto Neurath.Jordi Cat - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 38.
    Four distinguished authors have been brought together to produce this elegant study of a much-neglected figure. The book is divided into three sections: Neurath's biographical background and the economic and social context of his ideas; his theory of science; and the development of his role in debates on Marxist concepts of history and his own conception of science. Coinciding with the emerging serious interest in logical positivism, this timely publication will redress a current imbalance in the history and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  36.  2
    Epistemic representation beyond models: thought experiments, specimens, and pictures.Lorenzo Sartori - unknown
    Scientists often make use of epistemic representations in order to perform investigations about the real world. So far, philosophers of science interested in epistemic representation of this sort have mostly focused on scientific models. In this thesis, I argue that there are other interesting instances of representation besides models: thought experiments, experimental organisms, and mechanically-produced pictures. These represent portions of the world in the same way as models do, if the concept of epistemic representation is properly understood. In Chapter (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  33
    The role of models in the application of scientific theories: epistemological implications.Mauricio Suárez - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  38.  28
    The role of models in the application of scientific theories: epistemological implications.Mauricio Suárez - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  39.  10
    Epistemic landscapes, optimal search and the division of cognitive labor.J. McKenzie Alexander, Johannes Himmelreich & Christopher Thompson - 2015 - Philosophy of Science 82 (3):424-453.
    This paper examines two questions about scientists’ search for knowledge. First, which search strategies generate discoveries effectively? Second, is it advantageous to diversify search strategies? We argue pace Weisberg and Muldoon (2009) that, on the first question, a search strategy that deliberately seeks novel research approaches need not be optimal. On the second question, we argue they have not shown epistemic reasons exist for the division of cognitive labor, identifying the errors that led to their conclusions. Furthermore, we generalize the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  40.  17
    (1 other version)Scientific representation.Edward N. Zalta - 2012 - In Ed Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Science provides us with representations of atoms, elementary particles, polymers, populations, genetic trees, economies, rational decisions, aeroplanes, earthquakes, forest fires, irrigation systems, and the world’s climate. It's through these representations that we learn about the world. This entry explores various different accounts of scientific representation, with a particular focus on how scientific models represent their target systems. As philosophers of science are increasingly acknowledging the importance, if not the primacy, of scientific models as representational units of science, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41.  13
    (1 other version)Why typicality does not explain the approach to equilibrium.Roman Frigg - 2010 - In Mauricio Suárez (ed.), Probabilities, Causes and Propensities in Physics. New York: Springer. pp. 77-93.
    Why do systems prepared in a non-equilibrium state approach, and eventually reach, equilibrium? An important contemporary version of the Boltzmannian approach to statistical mechanics answers this question by an appeal to the notion of typicality. The problem with this approach is that it comes in different versions, which are, however, not recognised as such, much less clearly distinguished, and we often find different arguments pursued side by side. The aim of this paper is to disentangle different versions of typicality-based explanations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  42.  82
    What can polysemy tell us about theories of explanation?Maria Şerban - 2017 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 7 (1):41-56.
    Philosophical accounts of scientific explanation are broadly divided into ontic and epistemic views. This paper explores the idea that the lexical ambiguity of the verb to explain and its nominalisation supports an ontic conception of explanation (Salmon 1989; Craver 2007). I analyse one argument which challenges this strategy by criticising the claim that explanatory talk is lexically ambiguous (Wright, European Journal of Philosophy of Science 2(3), 375–394, 2012). I propose that the linguistic mechanism of transfer of meaning (Nunberg, Journal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43. (1 other version)Models and fiction.Roman Frigg - 2007 - Synthese 172 (2):251-268.
    Most scientific models are not physical objects, and this raises important questions. What sort of entity are models, what is truth in a model, and how do we learn about models? In this paper I argue that models share important aspects in common with literary fiction, and that therefore theories of fiction can be brought to bear on these questions. In particular, I argue that the pretence theory as developed by Walton (1990, Mimesis as make-believe: on the foundations of the (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  44.  7
    Probabilistic forecasting: why model imperfection is a poison pill.Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao Gonzalez, Thomas Ubel & Gregory Wheeler - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 479-492.
    This volume is a serious attempt to open up the subject of European philosophy of science to real thought, and provide the structural basis for the interdisciplinary development of its specialist fields, but also to provoke reflection on the idea of ‘European philosophy of science’. This efforts should foster a contemporaneous reflection on what might be meant by philosophy of science in Europe and European philosophy of science, and how in fact awareness of it could assist (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  8
    (1 other version)Machine guessing I.David Miller - unknown
    According to Karl Popper, the evolution of science, logically, methodologically, and even psychologically, is an involved interplay of acute conjectures and blunt refutations. Like biological evolution, it is an endless round of blind variation and selective retention. But unlike biological evolution, it incorporates, at the stage of selection, the use of reason. Part I of this two-part paper begins by repudiating the common beliefs that Hume’s problem of induction, which compellingly confutes the thesis that science is rational in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  41
    Models and representation: why structures are not enough.Roman Frigg - 2002 - London School of Economics and Political Science.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47.  16
    (1 other version)A field guide to recent work on the foundations of statistical mechanics.Roman Frigg - 2008 - In Dean Rickles (ed.), The Ashgate Companion to Contemporary Philosophy of Physics. Ashgate. pp. 99-196.
  48. Definable categorical equivalence.Laurenz Hudetz - 2019 - Philosophy of Science 86 (1):47-75.
    This article proposes to explicate theoretical equivalence by supplementing formal equivalence criteria with preservation conditions concerning interpretation. I argue that both the internal structure of models and choices of morphisms are aspects of formalisms that are relevant when it comes to their interpretation. Hence, a formal criterion suitable for being supplemented with preservation conditions concerning interpretation should take these two aspects into account. The two currently most important criteria—gener-alized definitional equivalence (Morita equivalence) and categorical equivalence—are not optimal in this respect. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  49.  39
    (1 other version)Pragmatic factors in theory-acceptance.John Worrall - 2000 - In W. Newton-Smith (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 349-357.
    The state of science at any given time is characterized, in part at least, by the theories that are accepted at that time. Presently accepted theories include quantum theory, the general theory of relativity, and the modern synthesis of Darwin and Mendel, as well as lower‐level (but still clearly theoretical) assertions such as that DNA has a double‐helical structure, that the hydrogen atom contains a single electron, and so on. What precisely is involved in accepting a theory?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  13
    Models and the limits of theory: quantum hamiltonians and the BCS model of superconductivity.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 241-281.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
1 — 50 / 134