Results for 'Logical equivalence of contrapositive'

964 found
Order:
  1.  48
    Sequent Calculi for the Propositional Logic of HYPE.Martin Fischer - 2021 - Studia Logica 110 (3):1-35.
    In this paper we discuss sequent calculi for the propositional fragment of the logic of HYPE. The logic of HYPE was recently suggested by Leitgeb as a logic for hyperintensional contexts. On the one hand we introduce a simple \-system employing rules of contraposition. On the other hand we present a \-system with an admissible rule of contraposition. Both systems are equivalent as well as sound and complete proof-system of HYPE. In order to provide a cut-elimination procedure, we expand the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  58
    Sātmaka, Nairātmya, and A-Nairātmya: Dharmakīrti’s Counter-Argument Against the Proof of Ātman. [REVIEW]Kyo Kano - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):391-410.
    Ātman (soul) and Nairātmya (no soul) are, for the Brahmanical schools and the Buddhists respectively, equally fundamental tenets which neither side can concede to the other. Among the 16 formulations presented by Uddyotakara, the fifteenth, which is a proof of Ātman and is originally an indirect proof ( avīta/āvīta ), is presented in a prasaṅga -style, and contains double negation ( na nairātmyam ) in the thesis. However, it is perhaps Dharmakīrti who first transformed it into a normal style ( (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  44
    On the contrapositive of countable choice.Hajime Ishihara & Peter Schuster - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (1-2):137-143.
    We show that in elementary analysis (EL) the contrapositive of countable choice is equivalent to double negation elimination for \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\Sigma_{2}^{0}}$$\end{document}-formulas. By also proving a recursive adaptation of this equivalence in Heyting arithmetic (HA), we give an instance of the conservativity of EL over HA with respect to recursive functions and predicates. As a complement, we prove in HA enriched with the (extended) Church thesis that every decidable predicate is recursive.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Extensions of the basic constructive logic for weak consistency BKc1 defined with a falsity constant.Gemma Robles - 2007 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 16 (4):311-322.
    The logic BKc1 is the basic constructive logic for weak consistency in the ternary relational semantics without a set of designated points. In this paper, a number of extensions of B Kc1 defined with a propositional falsity constant are defined. It is also proved that weak consistency is not equivalent to negation-consistency or absolute consistency in any logic included in positive contractionless intermediate logic LC plus the constructive negation of BKc1 and the contraposition axioms.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  29
    On the Uniform Computational Content of the Baire Category Theorem.Vasco Brattka, Matthew Hendtlass & Alexander P. Kreuzer - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (4):605-636.
    We study the uniform computational content of different versions of the Baire category theorem in the Weihrauch lattice. The Baire category theorem can be seen as a pigeonhole principle that states that a complete metric space cannot be decomposed into countably many nowhere dense pieces. The Baire category theorem is an illuminating example of a theorem that can be used to demonstrate that one classical theorem can have several different computational interpretations. For one, we distinguish two different logical versions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Almost everywhere equivalence of logics in finite model theory.Lauri Hella, Phokion G. Kolaitis & Kerkko Luosto - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):422-443.
    We introduce a new framework for classifying logics on finite structures and studying their expressive power. This framework is based on the concept of almost everywhere equivalence of logics, that is to say, two logics having the same expressive power on a class of asymptotic measure 1. More precisely, if L, L ′ are two logics and μ is an asymptotic measure on finite structures, then $\scr{L}\equiv _{\text{a.e.}}\scr{L}^{\prime}(\mu)$ means that there is a class C of finite structures with μ (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  7.  53
    Negative Equivalence of Extensions of Minimal Logic.Sergei P. Odintsov - 2004 - Studia Logica 78 (3):417-442.
    Two logics L1 and L2 are negatively equivalent if for any set of formulas X and any negated formula ¬, ¬ can be deduced from the set of hypotheses X in L1 if and only if it can be done in L2. This article is devoted to the investigation of negative equivalence relation in the class of extensions of minimal logic.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  8
    The Fan Theorem, its strong negation, and the determinacy of games.Wim Veldman - forthcoming - Archive for Mathematical Logic:1-66.
    In the context of a weak formal theory called Basic Intuitionistic Mathematics $$\textsf{BIM}$$ BIM, we study Brouwer’s Fan Theorem and a strong negation of the Fan Theorem, Kleene’s Alternative (to the Fan Theorem). We prove that the Fan Theorem is equivalent to contrapositions of a number of intuitionistically accepted axioms of countable choice and that Kleene’s Alternative is equivalent to strong negations of these statements. We discuss finite and infinite games and introduce a constructively useful notion of determinacy. We prove (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  27
    Expressive equivalence of least and inflationary fixed-point logic.Stephan Kreutzer - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 130 (1-3):61-78.
    We study the relationship between least and inflationary fixed-point logic. In 1986, Gurevich and Shelah proved that in the restriction to finite structures, the two logics have the same expressive power. On infinite structures however, the question whether there is a formula in IFP not equivalent to any LFP-formula was left open.In this paper, we answer the question negatively, i.e. we show that the two logics are equally expressive on arbitrary structures. We give a syntactic translation of IFP-formulae to LFP-formulae (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  11
    Logical Equivalence.Stephen Neale - 2001 - In Facing Facts. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Chs. 8 and 9 convert the two basic forms of slingshot argument—one used by Alonzo Church, W. V. Quine, and Donald Davidson, the other by Kurt Gödel—into knock‐down deductive proofs that Donald Davidson's and Richard Rorty's cases against facts and the representation of facts are unfounded, and their slingshot arguments for discrediting the existence of facts unsatisfactory. The proofs are agnostic on key semantic issues; in particular, they assume no particular account of reference and do not even assume that sentences (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  25
    An Extended Paradefinite Logic Combining Conflation, Paraconsistent Negation, Classical Negation, and Classical Implication: How to Construct Nice Gentzen-type Sequent Calculi.Norihiro Kamide - 2022 - Logica Universalis 16 (3):389-417.
    In this study, an extended paradefinite logic with classical negation (EPLC), which has the connectives of conflation, paraconsistent negation, classical negation, and classical implication, is introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. The logic EPLC is regarded as a modification of Arieli, Avron, and Zamansky’s ideal four-valued paradefinite logic (4CC) and as an extension of De and Omori’s extended Belnap–Dunn logic with classical negation (BD+) and Avron’s self-extensional four-valued paradefinite logic (SE4). The completeness, cut-elimination, and decidability theorems for EPLC are proved (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    Behavioral equivalence of hidden k -logics: An abstract algebraic approach.Sergey Babenyshev & Manuel A. Martins - 2016 - Journal of Applied Logic 16:72-91.
  13.  18
    Fundamentals of mathematical proof.Charles A. Matthews - 2018 - [place of publication not identified]: [Publisher Not Identified].
    This mathematics textbook covers the fundamental ideas used in writing proofs. Proof techniques covered include direct proofs, proofs by contrapositive, proofs by contradiction, proofs in set theory, proofs of existentially or universally quantified predicates, proofs by cases, and mathematical induction. Inductive and deductive reasoning are explored. A straightforward approach is taken throughout. Plenty of examples are included and lots of exercises are provided after each brief exposition on the topics at hand. The text begins with a study of symbolic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Paradoxes of Logical Equivalence and Identity.Andrew Bacon - 2013 - Topoi (1):1-10.
    In this paper a principle of substitutivity of logical equivalents salve veritate and a version of Leibniz’s law are formulated and each is shown to cause problems when combined with naive truth theories.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  32
    Two Kinds of Consequential Implication.Claudio E. A. Pizzi - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (3):453-480.
    The first section of the paper establishes the minimal properties of so-called consequential implication and shows that they are satisfied by at least two different operators of decreasing strength and \). Only the former has been analyzed in recent literature, so the paper focuses essentially on the latter. Both operators may be axiomatized in systems which are shown to be translatable into standard systems of normal modal logic. The central result of the paper is that the minimal consequential system for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Nomological necessity and the paradoxes of confirmation.Brian Skyrms - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (3):230-249.
    Some of the concerns which motivate attempts to provide a philosophical reduction of nomological necessity are briefly introduced in I. In II, Hempel's treatment of the paradoxes is contrasted with a position which holds that nomological necessity is a pragmatic dimension of laws of nature, and that this pragmatic dimension is of such a type that it prevents laws of nature from contraposing. Such a position is, however, untenable unless (i) the sense of 'pragmatics' at issue is specified, and the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17. Why Logically Equivalent Predicates May Pick out Different Properties.Elliott Sober - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (2):183-189.
    The properties, theoretical magnitudes, and natural kinds which science seeks to characterize, and not the sense or meanings which parts of speech may possess, are the subject of this paper. Many philosophers (e.g., Putnam [1971] and Achinstein [1974]) have agreed that two predicates of different meaning may pick out the same property, but they usually hold that that logically equivalent predicates must pick out the same properties. I propose to deny this thesis. My argument is by way of an example (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  18.  63
    Commutative basic algebras and non-associative fuzzy logics.Michal Botur & Radomír Halaš - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (3-4):243-255.
    Several investigations in probability theory and the theory of expert systems show that it is important to search for some reasonable generalizations of fuzzy logics (e.g. Łukasiewicz, Gödel or product logic) having a non-associative conjunction. In the present paper, we offer a non-associative fuzzy logic L CBA having as an equivalent algebraic semantics lattices with section antitone involutions satisfying the contraposition law, so-called commutative basic algebras. The class (variety) CBA of commutative basic algebras was intensively studied in several recent papers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  19
    On the equivalence of the Meskhi and Cignoli conditions for p-algebras with involution, with application to Lukasiewicz 3 and 4 valued logics. [REVIEW]George Epstein - 1977 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 6 (4):156-159.
    In a recent issue of this Bulletin, S. Meskhi cites 7 additional conditions for Heyting algebras with involution and linearly ordered matrix [10, p. 11]. In [2], R. Cignoli indicates 3 additional conditions for P-algebras [5] with normal involution [9]. The equivalence of these conditions is shown.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    Logical characterizations of regular equivalence in weighted social networks.Tuan-Fang Fan & Churn-Jung Liau - 2014 - Artificial Intelligence 214 (C):66-88.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  81
    (2 other versions)Categorical abstract algebraic logic: Equivalent institutions.George Voutsadakis - 2003 - Studia Logica 74 (1-2):275 - 311.
    A category theoretic generalization of the theory of algebraizable deductive systems of Blok and Pigozzi is developed. The theory of institutions of Goguen and Burstall is used to provide the underlying framework which replaces and generalizes the universal algebraic framework based on the notion of a deductive system. The notion of a term -institution is introduced first. Then the notions of quasi-equivalence, strong quasi-equivalence and deductive equivalence are defined for -institutions. Necessary and sufficient conditions are given for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  22.  17
    On the equivalence of systems of rules and systems of axioms in illative combinatory logic.M. W. Bunder - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (3):603-608.
  23.  44
    The Equivalence of Tree Adjoining Grammars and Monadic Linear Context-free Tree Grammars.Stephan Kepser & Jim Rogers - 2011 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (3):361-384.
    The equivalence of leaf languages of tree adjoining grammars and monadic linear context-free grammars was shown about a decade ago. This paper presents a proof of the strong equivalence of these grammar formalisms. Non-strict tree adjoining grammars and monadic linear context-free grammars define the same class of tree languages. We also present a logical characterisation of this tree language class showing that a tree language is a member of this class iff it is the two-dimensional yield of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  78
    Coherence as Generalized Logical Equivalence.Wouter Meijs - 2006 - Erkenntnis 64 (2):231-252.
    In this paper I consider whether there is a measure of coherence that could be rightly claimed to generalize the notion of logical equivalence. I show that Fitelson’s (2003) proposal to that effect encounters some serious difficulties. Furthermore, there is reason to believe that no mutual-support measure could ever be suitable for the formalization of coherence as generalized logical equivalence. Instead, it appears that the only plausible candidate for such a measure is one of relative overlap. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  25. Logically Equivalent False Universal Propositions with Different Counterexample Sets.John Corcoran - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11:554-5.
    This paper corrects a mistake I saw students make but I have yet to see in print. The mistake is thinking that logically equivalent propositions have the same counterexamples—always. Of course, it is often the case that logically equivalent propositions have the same counterexamples: “every number that is prime is odd” has the same counterexamples as “every number that is not odd is not prime”. The set of numbers satisfying “prime but not odd” is the same as the set of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  35
    Homeomorphism and the Equivalence of Logical Systems.Stephen Pollard - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (3):422-435.
    Say that a property is topological if and only if it is invariant under homeomorphism. Homeomorphism would be a successful criterion for the equivalence of logical systems only if every logically significant property of every logical system were topological. Alas, homeomorphisms are sometimes insensitive to distinctions that logicians value: properties such as functional completeness are not topological. So logics are not just devices for exploring closure topologies. One still wonders, though, how much of logic is topological. This (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. On the logical status of equivalence principles in general relativity theory.Mendel Sachs - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (3):225-229.
  28.  61
    N-prolog and equivalence of logic programs.Nicola Olivetti & Lea Terracini - 1992 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 1 (4):253-340.
    The aim of this work is to develop a declarative semantics for N-Prolog with negation as failure. N-Prolog is an extension of Prolog proposed by Gabbay and Reyle, which allows for occurrences of nested implications in both goals and clauses. Our starting point is an operational semantics of the language defined by means of top-down derivation trees. Negation as finite failure can be naturally introduced in this context. A goal-G may be inferred from a database if every top-down derivation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Com 1 models of pouer to.L. -Elementarily Equivalent - 1981 - In Manuel Lerman, James Henry Schmerl & Robert Irving Soare (eds.), Logic year 1979-80, the University of Connecticut, USA. New York: Springer Verlag. pp. 859--120.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  22
    The Weakness of Logical Equivalence”.Paul Weingartner - 1998 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 27:46-49.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Equivalence of defeasible normative systems.José Júlio Alferes, Ricardo Gonçalves & João Leite - 2013 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 23 (1-2):25-48.
    Normative systems have been advocated as an effective tool to regulate interaction in multi-agent systems. The use of deontic operators and the ability to represent defeasible information are known to be two fundamental ingredients to represent and reason about normative systems. In this paper, after introducing a framework that combines standard deontic logic and non-monotonic logic programming, deontic logic programs (DLP), we tackle the fundamental problem of equivalence between normative systems using a deontic extension of David Pearce’s Equilibrium Logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  24
    The equivalence of Axiom [math] and Axiom [math].W. Hugh Woodin - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Ahead of Print. Asperó and Schindler have completely solved the Axiom [math] vs. [math] problem. They have proved that if [math] holds then Axiom [math] holds, with no additional assumptions. The key question now concerns the relationship between [math] and Axiom [math]. This is because the foundational issues raised by the problem of Axiom [math] vs. [math] arguably persist in the problem of Axiom [math] vs. [math]. The first of our two main theorems is that Axiom (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  58
    (1 other version)Fragments of Heyting arithmetic.Wolfgang Burr - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1223-1240.
    We define classes Φnof formulae of first-order arithmetic with the following properties:(i) Everyφϵ Φnis classically equivalent to a Πn-formula (n≠ 1, Φ1:= Σ1).(ii)(iii)IΠnandiΦn(i.e., Heyting arithmetic with induction schema restricted to Φn-formulae) prove the same Π2-formulae.We further generalize a result by Visser and Wehmeier. namely that prenex induction within intuitionistic arithmetic is rather weak: After closing Φnboth under existential and universal quantification (we call these classes Θn) the corresponding theoriesiΘnstill prove the same Π2-formulae. In a second part we consideriΔ0plus collection-principles. We (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  34.  86
    Equivalence of consequence relations: an order-theoretic and categorical perspective.Nikolaos Galatos & Constantine Tsinakis - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (3):780-810.
    Equivalences and translations between consequence relations abound in logic. The notion of equivalence can be defined syntactically, in terms of translations of formulas, and order-theoretically, in terms of the associated lattices of theories. W. Blok and D. Pigozzi proved in [4] that the two definitions coincide in the case of an algebraizable sentential deductive system. A refined treatment of this equivalence was provided by W. Blok and B. Jónsson in [3]. Other authors have extended this result to the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  35.  68
    Equivalents of the (weak) fan theorem.Iris Loeb - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 132 (1):51-66.
    This article presents a weak system of intuitionistic second-order arithmetic, WKV, a subsystem of the one in S.C. Kleene, R.E. Vesley [The Foundations of Intuitionistic Mathematics: Especially in Relation to Recursive Functions, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1965]. It is then shown that some statements of real analysis, like a version of the Heine–Borel Theorem, and some statements of logic, e.g. compactness of classical proposition calculus, are equivalent to the Fan Theorem in this system.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  36.  39
    Equivalents of the finitary non-deterministic inductive definitions.Ayana Hirata, Hajime Ishihara, Tatsuji Kawai & Takako Nemoto - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (10):1256-1272.
    We present statements equivalent to some fragments of the principle of non-deterministic inductive definitions (NID) by van den Berg (2013), working in a weak subsystem of constructive set theory CZF. We show that several statements in constructive topology which were initially proved using NID are equivalent to the elementary and finitary NIDs. We also show that the finitary NID is equivalent to its binary fragment and that the elementary NID is equivalent to a variant of NID based on the notion (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  45
    Equivalence of Problems (An Attempt at an Explication of Problem).Pavel Materna - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (4):617-631.
    On the one hand, Pavel Tichý has shown in his Transparent Intensional Logic (TIL) that the best way of explicating meaning of the expressions of a natural language consists in identification of meanings with abstract procedures. TIL explicates objective abstract procedures as so-called constructions. Constructions that do not contain free variables and are in a well-defined sense ´normalized´ are called concepts in TIL. On the second hand, Kolmogorov in (Mathematische Zeitschrift 35: 58–65, 1932) formulated a theory of problems, using NL (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  62
    'The devil's dilemma in Flaubert' saint Antony.Dale Jacquette - 1998 - Heythrop Journal 39 (2):140–147.
    In La Téntation de Saint Antoine Gustave Flaubert dramatizes a philosophical exchange about the nature of divine providence and the efficacy of petitionary prayer. The Devil and Antony consider the question of whether God can be called upon for relief from suffering. The Saint assumes as popular religion teaches that it is possible to ask for God's help in emergency situations, while the Devil poses a dilemma to challenge Antony's faith. The Devil seeks to expose contradictions in some of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  62
    Elementary equivalence of some rings of definable functions.Vincent Astier - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (4):327-340.
    We characterize elementary equivalences and inclusions between von Neumann regular real closed rings in terms of their boolean algebras of idempotents, and prove that their theories are always decidable. We then show that, under some hypotheses, the map sending an L-structure R to the L-structure of definable functions from R n to R preserves elementary inclusions and equivalences and gives a structure with a decidable theory whenever R is decidable. We briefly consider structures of definable functions satisfying an extra condition (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  91
    The equivalence of theories that characterize ALogTime.Phuong Nguyen - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (6):523-549.
    A number of theories have been developed to characterize ALogTime (or uniform NC 1, or just NC 1), the class of languages accepted by alternating logtime Turing machines, in the same way that Buss’s theory ${{\bf S}^{1}_{2}}$ characterizes polytime functions. Among these, ALV′ (by Clote) is particularly interesting because it is developed based on Barrington’s theorem that the word problem for the permutation group S 5 is complete for ALogTime. On the other hand, ALV (by Clote), T 0 NC 0 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  31
    Testing Definitional Equivalence of Theories Via Automorphism Groups.Hajnal Andréka, Judit Madarász, István Németi & Gergely Székely - 2024 - Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (4):1097-1118.
    Two first-order logic theories are definitionally equivalent if and only if there is a bijection between their model classes that preserves isomorphisms and ultraproducts (Theorem 2). This is a variant of a prior theorem of van Benthem and Pearce. In Example 2, uncountably many pairs of definitionally inequivalent theories are given such that their model categories are concretely isomorphic via bijections that preserve ultraproducts in the model categories up to isomorphism. Based on these results, we settle several conjectures of Barrett, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  33
    Equivalence of bar induction and bar recursion for continuous functions with continuous moduli.Makoto Fujiwara & Tatsuji Kawai - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (8):867-890.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  54
    The equivalence of determinacy and iterated sharps.Derrick Albert Dubose - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):502-525.
    We characterize, in terms of determinacy, the existence of 0 ♯♯ as well as the existence of each of the following: 0 ♯♯♯ , 0 ♯♯♯♯ ,0 ♯♯♯♯♯ , .... For k ∈ ω, we define two classes of sets, (k * Σ 0 1 ) * and (k * Σ 0 1 ) * + , which lie strictly between $\bigcup_{\beta and Δ(ω 2 -Π 1 1 ). We also define 0 1♯ as 0 ♯ and in general, 0 (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  24
    On the Transparency of Defeasible Logics: Equivalent Premise Sets, Equivalence of Their Extensions, and Maximality of the Lower Limit.Diderik Batens, Christian Strasser & Peter Verdée - 2009 - Logique Et Analyse 52 (207):281-304.
    For Tarski logics, there are simple criteria that enable one to conclude that two premise sets are equivalent. We shall show that the very same criteria hold for adaptive logics, which is a major advantage in comparison to other approaches to defeasible reasoning forms. A related property of Tarski logics is that the extensions of equivalent premise sets with the same set of formulas are equivalent premise sets. This does not hold for adaptive logics. However a very similar criterion does. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  60
    Equivalents of Mingle and positive paradox.Eric Schechter - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (1):117 - 128.
    Relevant logic is a proper subset of classical logic. It does not include among its theorems any ofpositive paradox A (B A).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  46
    The equivalence of a generalized Martin's axiom to a combinatorial principle.William Weiss - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):817-821.
    A generalized version of Martin's axiom, called BACH, is shown to be equivalent to one of its combinatorial consequences, a generalization of P(c).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  8
    Equivalence of generics.Iian B. Smythe - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (5):795-812.
    Given a countable transitive model of set theory and a partial order contained in it, there is a natural countable Borel equivalence relation on generic filters over the model; two are equivalent if they yield the same generic extension. We examine the complexity of this equivalence relation for various partial orders, focusing on Cohen and random forcing. We prove, among other results, that the former is an increasing union of countably many hyperfinite Borel equivalence relations, and hence (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    On the equivalence of Ajdukiewicz-Lambek calculus and simple phrase structure grammars.Wojciech Zielonka - 1976 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 5 (2):1-4.
    In [2], Bar-Hillel, Gaifman, and Shamir prove that the simple phrase structure grammars dened by Chomsky are equivalent in a cer- tain sense to Bar-Hillel's bidirectional categorial grammars . On the other hand, Cohen [3] proves the equivalence of the latter ones to what he calls free categorial grammars . They are closely related to Lambek's syntactic calculus which is, in turn, based on the idea due to Ajdukiewicz [1]. For some reasons, Cohen's proof seems to be at least (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  47
    The equivalence of the disjunction and existence properties for modal arithmetic.Harvey Friedman & Michael Sheard - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1456-1459.
    In a modal system of arithmetic, a theory S has the modal disjunction property if whenever $S \vdash \square\varphi \vee \square\psi$ , either $S \vdash \square\varphi$ or $S \vdash \square\psi. S$ has the modal numerical existence property if whenever $S \vdash \exists x\square\varphi(x)$ , there is some natural number n such that $S \vdash \square\varphi(\mathbf{n})$ . Under certain broadly applicable assumptions, these two properties are equivalent.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  57
    The equivalence of bar recursion and open recursion.Thomas Powell - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (11):1727-1754.
    Several extensions of Gödel's system TT with new forms of recursion have been designed for the purpose of giving a computational interpretation to classical analysis. One can organise many of these extensions into two groups: those based on bar recursion , which include Spector's original bar recursion, modified bar recursion and the more recent products of selections functions, or those based on open recursion which in particular include the symmetric Berardi–Bezem–Coquand functional. We relate these two groups by showing that both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 964