Results for 'Dedekind infinite set'

966 found
Order:
  1.  19
    Sequential topologies and Dedekind finite sets.Jindřich Zapletal - 2022 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 68 (1):107-109.
    It is consistent with ZF $\mathsf {ZF}$ set theory that the Euclidean topology on R $\mathbb {R}$ is not sequential, yet every infinite set of reals contains a countably infinite subset. This answers a question of Gutierres.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  74
    Why Believe Infinite Sets Exist?Andrei Mărăşoiu - 2018 - Axiomathes 28 (4):447-460.
    The axiom of infinity states that infinite sets exist. I will argue that this axiom lacks justification. I start by showing that the axiom is not self-evident, so it needs separate justification. Following Maddy’s :481–511, 1988) distinction, I argue that the axiom of infinity lacks both intrinsic and extrinsic justification. Crucial to my project is Skolem’s From Frege to Gödel: a source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, pp. 290–301, 1922) distinction between a theory of real (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  28
    A Note on Weakly Dedekind Finite Sets.Pimpen Vejjajiva & Supakun Panasawatwong - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (3):413-417.
    A set $A$ is Dedekind infinite if there is a one-to-one function from $\omega$ into $A$. A set $A$ is weakly Dedekind infinite if there is a function from $A$ onto $\omega$; otherwise $A$ is weakly Dedekind finite. For a set $M$, let $\operatorname{dfin}^{*}$ denote the set of all weakly Dedekind finite subsets of $M$. In this paper, we prove, in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, that $|\operatorname{dfin}^{*}|\lt |\mathcal{P}|$ if $\operatorname{dfin}^{*}$ is Dedekind infinite, whereas (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  44
    The First-Order Structure of Weakly Dedekind-Finite Sets.A. C. Walczak-Typke - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (4):1161 - 1170.
    We show that infinite sets whose power-sets are Dedekind-finite can only carry N₀-categorical first order structures. We identify other subclasses of this class of Dedekind-finite sets, and discuss their possible first order structures.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  30
    Strongly Amorphous Sets and Dual Dedekind Infinity.Martin Goldstern - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (1):39-44.
    1. If A is strongly amorphous , then its power set P is dually Dedekind infinite, i. e., every function from P onto P is injective. 2. The class of “inexhaustible” sets is not closed under supersets unless AC holds.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  30
    A General Setting for Dedekind's Axiomatization of the Positive Integers.George Weaver - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (4):375-398.
    A Dedekind algebra is an ordered pair (B, h), where B is a non-empty set and h is a similarity transformation on B. Among the Dedekind algebras is the sequence of the positive integers. From a contemporary perspective, Dedekind established that the second-order theory of the sequence of the positive integers is categorical and finitely axiomatizable. The purpose here is to show that this seemingly isolated result is a consequence of more general results in the model theory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  51
    A dedekind finite borel set.Arnold W. Miller - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (1-2):1-17.
    In this paper we prove three theorems about the theory of Borel sets in models of ZF without any form of the axiom of choice. We prove that if \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${B\subseteq 2^\omega}$$\end{document} is a Gδσ-set then either B is countable or B contains a perfect subset. Second, we prove that if 2ω is the countable union of countable sets, then there exists an Fσδ set \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  36
    Factorials of infinite cardinals in zf part II: Consistency results.Guozhen Shen & Jiachen Yuan - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):244-270.
    For a set x, let S(x) be the set of all permutations of x. We prove by the method of permutation models that the following statements are consistent with ZF: (1) There is an infinite set x such that |p(x)|<|S(x)|<|seq^1-1(x)|<|seq(x)|, where p(x) is the powerset of x, seq(x) is the set of all finite sequences of elements of x, and seq^1-1(x) is the set of all finite sequences of elements of x without repetition. (2) There is a Dedekind (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. A Road Map of Dedekind’s Theorem 66.Ansten Klev - 2018 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 8 (2):241-277.
    Richard Dedekind’s theorem 66 states that there exists an infinite set. Its proof invokes such apparently nonmathematical notions as the thought-world and the self. This article discusses the content and context of Dedekind’s proof. It is suggested that Dedekind took the notion of the thought-world from Hermann Lotze. The influence of Kant and Bernard Bolzano on the proof is also discussed, and the reception of the proof in the mathematical and philosophical literature is covered in detail.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  22
    Factorials of infinite cardinals in zf part I: Zf results.Guozhen Shen & Jiachen Yuan - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):224-243.
    For a set x, let ${\cal S}\left$ be the set of all permutations of x. We prove in ZF several results concerning this notion, among which are the following: For all sets x such that ${\cal S}\left$ is Dedekind infinite, $\left| {{{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left} \right| < \left| {{\cal S}\left} \right|$ and there are no finite-to-one functions from ${\cal S}\left$ into ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$, where ${{\cal S}_{{\rm{fin}}}}\left$ denotes the set of all permutations of x which move only finitely many elements. For (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  11.  42
    Grammar of Infinity. Ludwig Wittgenstein's Critique of Set Theory.Piotr Dehnel - 2023 - Analiza I Egzystencja 63:55-87.
    The paper discusses a relatively underexamined element of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics associated with his critique of set theory. I outline Wittgenstein’s objections to the theories of Dedekind and Cantor, including the confounding of extension and intension, the faulty definition of the infinite set as infinite extension and the critique of Cantor’s diagonal proof. One of Wittgenstein’s major objections to set theory was that the concept of the size of infinite sets, which Cantor expressed by means (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  31
    On infinite‐dimensional Banach spaces and weak forms of the axiom of choice.Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (6):509-535.
    We study theorems from Functional Analysis with regard to their relationship with various weak choice principles and prove several results about them: “Every infinite‐dimensional Banach space has a well‐orderable Hamel basis” is equivalent to ; “ can be well‐ordered” implies “no infinite‐dimensional Banach space has a Hamel basis of cardinality ”, thus the latter statement is true in every Fraenkel‐Mostowski model of ; “No infinite‐dimensional Banach space has a Hamel basis of cardinality ” is not provable in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  25
    Infinity and the Self: Royce on Dedekind.Sébastien Gandon - 2021 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 11 (2):354-382.
    In Die Zahlen (1888), Dedekind defines an infinite set as a set that is isomorphic with one of its proper parts. In The World and the Individual (1900), the American philosopher Josiah Royce relates Dedekind’s notion to Fichte’s and Hegel’s concept of Self defined as an entity that reflects itself into itself. The first aim of this article is to explain Royce’s analysis and to put it in its proper context, that of a critique of Bradley’s mystical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  27
    Relations between cardinalities of the finite sequences and the finite subsets of a set.Navin Aksornthong & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (6):529-534.
    We write and for the cardinalities of the set of finite sequences and the set of finite subsets, respectively, of a set which is of cardinality. With the axiom of choice (), for every infinite cardinal but, without, any relationship between and for an arbitrary infinite cardinal cannot be proved. In this paper, we give conditions that make and comparable for an infinite cardinal. Among our results, we show that, if we assume the axiom of choice for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15. The Finite and the Infinite in Frege's Grundgesetze der Arithmetik.Richard Heck - 1998 - In Matthias Schirn (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics Today: Papers From a Conference Held in Munich From June 28 to July 4,1993. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Discusses Frege's formal definitions and characterizations of infinite and finite sets. Speculates that Frege might have discovered the "oddity" in Dedekind's famous proof that all infinite sets are Dedekind infinite and, in doing so, stumbled across an axiom of countable choice.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. The Finite and the Infinite in Frege's Grundgesetze der Arithmetik.Richard Heck - 1998 - In Matthias Schirn (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics Today: Papers From a Conference Held in Munich From June 28 to July 4,1993. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Discusses Frege's formal definitions and characterizations of infinite and finite sets. Speculates that Frege might have discovered the "oddity" in Dedekind's famous proof that all infinite sets are Dedekind infinite and, in doing so, stumbled across an axiom of countable choice.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  20
    The permutations with n non‐fixed points and the subsets with n elements of a set.Supakun Panasawatwong & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2023 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 69 (3):341-346.
    We write and for the cardinalities of the set of permutations with n non‐fixed points and the set of subsets with n elements, respectively, of a set which is of cardinality, where n is a natural number greater than 1. With the Axiom of Choice, and are equal for all infinite cardinals. We show, in ZF, that if is assumed, then for any infinite cardinal. Moreover, the assumption cannot be removed for and the superscript cannot be replaced by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Dedekind's proof.Andrew Boucher - manuscript
    In "The Nature and Meaning of Numbers," Dedekind produces an original, quite remarkable proof for the holy grail in the foundations of elementary arithmetic, that there are an infinite number of things. It goes like this. [p, 64 in the Dover edition.] Consider the set S of things which can be objects of my thought. Define the function phi(s), which maps an element s of S to the thought that s can be an object of my thought. Then (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  27
    Models of $${{\textsf{ZFA}}}$$ in which every linearly ordered set can be well ordered.Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (7):1131-1157.
    We provide a general criterion for Fraenkel–Mostowski models of $${\textsf{ZFA}}$$ (i.e. Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory weakened to permit the existence of atoms) which implies “every linearly ordered set can be well ordered” ( $${\textsf{LW}}$$ ), and look at six models for $${\textsf{ZFA}}$$ which satisfy this criterion (and thus $${\textsf{LW}}$$ is true in these models) and “every Dedekind finite set is finite” ( $${\textsf{DF}}={\textsf{F}}$$ ) is true, and also consider various forms of choice for well-ordered families of well orderable sets in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  34
    Finiteness Classes and Small Violations of Choice.Horst Herrlich, Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (3):375-388.
    We study properties of certain subclasses of the Dedekind finite sets in set theory without the axiom of choice with respect to the comparability of their elements and to the boundedness of such classes, and we answer related open problems from Herrlich’s “The Finite and the Infinite.” The main results are as follows: 1. It is relatively consistent with ZF that the class of all finite sets is not the only finiteness class such that any two of its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  27
    (1 other version)Powers of 2.Kyriakos Keremedis & Horst Herrlich - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):346-351.
    It is shown that in ZF Martin's -axiom together with the axiom of countable choice for finite sets imply that arbitrary powers 2X of a 2-point discrete space are Baire; and that the latter property implies the following: (a) the axiom of countable choice for finite sets, (b) power sets of infinite sets are Dedekind-infinite, (c) there are no amorphous sets, and (d) weak forms of the Kinna-Wagner principle.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  29
    Non‐discrete metrics in and some notions of finiteness.Kyriakos Keremedis - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (4-5):383-390.
    We show that (i) it is consistent with that there are infinite sets X on which every metric is discrete; (ii) the notion of real infinite is strictly stronger than that of metrically infinite; (iii) a set X is metrically infinite if and only if it is weakly Dedekindinfinite if and only if the cardinality of the set of all metrically finite subsets of X is strictly less than the size of ; and (iv) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  43
    No decreasing sequence of cardinals.Paul Howard & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3-4):415-429.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice, we investigate the set-theoretic strength of the principle NDS which states that there is no function f on the set ω of natural numbers such that for everyn ∈ ω, f ≺ f, where for sets x and y, x ≺ y means that there is a one-to-one map g : x → y, but no one-to-one map h : y → x. It is a long standing open problem whether NDS implies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  59
    Divisibility of dedekind finite sets.David Blair, Andreas Blass & Paul Howard - 2005 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 5 (1):49-85.
    A Dedekind-finite set is said to be divisible by a natural number n if it can be partitioned into pieces of size n. We study several aspects of this notion, as well as the stronger notion of being partitionable into n pieces of equal size. Among our results are that the divisors of a Dedekind-finite set can consistently be any set of natural numbers, that a Dedekind-finite power of 2 cannot be divisible by 3, and that a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  39
    James sequences and Dependent Choices.Marianne Morillon - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (2):171-186.
    We prove James's sequential characterization of reflexivity in set-theory ZF + DC, where DC is the axiom of Dependent Choices. In turn, James's criterion implies that every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite, whence it is not provable in ZF. Our proof in ZF + DC of James' criterion leads us to various notions of reflexivity which are equivalent in ZFC but are not equivalent in ZF. We also show that the weak compactness of the closed unit ball of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. La descente infinie, l’induction transfinie et le tiers exclu.Yvon Gauthier - 2009 - Dialogue 48 (1):1.
    ABSTRACT: It is argued that the equivalence, which is usually postulated to hold between infinite descent and transfinite induction in the foundations of arithmetic uses the law of excluded middle through the use of a double negation on the infinite set of natural numbers and therefore cannot be admitted in intuitionistic logic and mathematics, and a fortiori in more radical constructivist foundational schemes. Moreover it is shown that the infinite descent used in Dedekind-Peano arithmetic does not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  24
    Infinite sets that Satisfy the Principle of Omniscience in any Variety of Constructive Mathematics.Martín H. Escardó - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (3):764-784.
  28. Luck and Proportions of Infinite Sets.Roger Clarke - 2024 - Erkenntnis 89 (7):2947-2949.
    In this note, I point out a mathematically well-defined way of non-trivially comparing the sizes of uncountable sets of equal cardinality.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  29
    Infinite sets of nonequivalent modalities.Fabio Bellissima - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (4):574-582.
  30.  88
    Infinite set unification with application to categorial grammar.Jacek Marciniec - 1997 - Studia Logica 58 (3):339-355.
    In this paper the notion of unifier is extended to the infinite set case. The proof of existence of the most general unifier of any infinite, unifiable set of types (terms) is presented. Learning procedure, based on infinite set unification, is described.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  19
    Finite sets and infinite sets in weak intuitionistic arithmetic.Takako Nemoto - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (5-6):607-657.
    In this paper, we consider, for a set \ of natural numbers, the following notions of finitenessFIN1:There are a natural number l and a bijection f between \\);FIN5:It is not the case that \\), and infinitenessINF1:There are not a natural number l and a bijection f between \\);INF5:\\). In this paper, we systematically compare them in the method of constructive reverse mathematics. We show that the equivalence among them can be characterized by various combinations of induction axioms and non-constructive principles, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  85
    The Nuisance Principle in Infinite Settings.Sean C. Ebels-Duggan - 2015 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 4 (4):263-268.
    Neo-Fregeans have been troubled by the Nuisance Principle, an abstraction principle that is consistent but not jointly satisfiable with the favored abstraction principle HP. We show that logically this situation persists if one looks at joint consistency rather than satisfiability: under a modest assumption about infinite concepts, NP is also inconsistent with HP.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33.  34
    Combinatorial designs on infinite sets.William J. Frascella - 1967 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 8 (1-2):27-47.
  34.  53
    Probability and Infinite Sets.Thomas Bittner - 1993 - Cogito 7 (2):150-152.
  35.  1
    (1 other version)The unconscious as infinite sets: an essay in bi-logic.Ignacio Matte Blanco - 1975 - London: Duckworth.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  36.  51
    Quantitative relations between infinite sets.Robert Bunn - 1977 - Annals of Science 34 (2):177-191.
    Given the old conception of the relation greater than, the proposition that the whole is greater than the part is an immediate consequence. But being greater in this sense is not incompatible with being equal in the sense of one-one correspondence. Some who failed to recognize this formulated invalid arguments against the possibility of infinite quantities. Others who did realize that the relations of equal and greater when so defined are compatible, concluded that such relations are not appropriately taken (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  41
    Markov's principle, isols and Dedekind finite sets.Charles McCarty - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (4):1042-1069.
  38.  45
    Syllogistic Logic with Cardinality Comparisons, on Infinite Sets.Lawrence S. Moss & Selçuk Topal - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):1-22.
    This article enlarges classical syllogistic logic with assertions having to do with comparisons between the sizes of sets. So it concerns a logical system whose sentences are of the following forms: Allxareyand Somexarey, There are at least as manyxasy, and There are morexthany. Herexandyrange over subsets (not elements) of a giveninfiniteset. Moreover,xandymay appear complemented (i.e., as$\bar{x}$and$\bar{y}$), with the natural meaning. We formulate a logic for our language that is based on the classical syllogistic. The main result is a soundness/completeness theorem. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  33
    A stronger definition of a recursively infinite set.Charles H. Applebaum - 1973 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (3):411-412.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  27
    A stronger theorem concerning the non-existence of combinatorial designs on infinite sets.William J. Frascella - 1973 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (4):554-558.
  41.  20
    The non-existence of a certain combinatorial design on an infinite set.William J. Frascella - 1969 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 10 (3):317-323.
  42.  13
    Self-Awareness in Nishida as Auto-Realization qua Determination of the Indeterminate.John W. M. Krummel - 2023 - In Saulius Geniusas (ed.), Varieties of Self-Awareness: New Perspectives from Phenomenology, Hermeneutics, and Comparative Philosophy. Springer Verlag. pp. 173-192.
    This chapter tracks the development of the concept of self-awareness (jikaku, 自覚) in the thought of the Japanese modern philosopher Nishida Kitarō (西田幾多郎) (Kitarō Nishida) (1870–1945), founder of the Kyoto School. Nishida’s oeuvre can be divided into distinct periods, from the 1910s to the 1940s until his passing, during which he thematized and focused on different issues. Nevertheless, self-awareness is a unifying theme throughout. In the chapter we trace how Nishida develops this concept through distinct periods in his career. His (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  71
    Infinite lotteries, large and small sets.Luc Lauwers - 2017 - Synthese 194 (6):2203-2209.
    One result of this note is about the nonconstructivity of countably infinite lotteries: even if we impose very weak conditions on the assignment of probabilities to subsets of natural numbers we cannot prove the existence of such assignments constructively, i.e., without something such as the axiom of choice. This is a corollary to a more general theorem about large-small filters, a concept that extends the concept of free ultrafilters. The main theorem is that proving the existence of large-small filters (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  64
    Monotone reducibility and the family of infinite sets.Douglas Cenzer - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3):774-782.
    Let A and B be subsets of the space 2 N of sets of natural numbers. A is said to be Wadge reducible to B if there is a continuous map Φ from 2 N into 2 N such that A = Φ -1 (B); A is said to be monotone reducible to B if in addition the map Φ is monotone, that is, $a \subset b$ implies $\Phi (a) \subset \Phi(b)$ . The set A is said to be monotone (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  56
    (1 other version)On infinite size.Bruno Whittle - 2015 - Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 9:3-19.
    This chapter challenges Cantor’s notion of the ‘power’, or ‘cardinality’, of an infinite set. According to Cantor, two infinite sets have the same cardinality if and only if there is a one-to-one correspondence between them. Cantor showed that there are infinite sets that do not have the same cardinality in this sense. Further, he took this result to show that there are infinite sets of different sizes. This has become the standard understanding of the result. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46.  33
    An early fifteenth century discussion of infinite sets.E. J. Ashworth - 1977 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 18 (2):232-234.
  47. A crash course in the mathematics of infinite sets.Peter Suber - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Infinite Opinion Sets and Relative Accuracy.Ilho Park & Jaemin Jung - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy 120 (6):285-313.
    We can have credences in an infinite number of propositions—that is, our opinion set can be infinite. Accuracy-first epistemologists have devoted themselves to evaluating credal states with the help of the concept of ‘accuracy’. Unfortunately, under several innocuous assumptions, infinite opinion sets yield several undesirable results, some of which are even fatal, to accuracy-first epistemology. Moreover, accuracy-first epistemologists cannot circumvent these difficulties in any standard way. In this regard, we will suggest a non-standard approach, called a relativistic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  59
    A set mapping with no infinite free subsets.P. Komjáth - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1400 - 1402.
    It is consistent that there exists a set mapping $F: \lbrack\omega_2\rbrack^2 \rightarrow \lbrack\omega_2\rbrack^{<\omega}$ such that $F(\alpha, \beta) \subseteq \alpha$ for $\alpha < \beta < \omega_2$ and there is no infinite free subset for F. This solves a problem of A. Hajnal and A. Mate.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  22
    Certain counterexamples to the construction of combinatorial designs on infinite sets.William J. Frascella - 1971 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 12 (4):461-466.
1 — 50 / 966