The Nonconceptual Representational Content of Perceptual Experience

Dissertation, Temple University (1999)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

It is argued that perceptual experience, at its most basic levels, has a nonconceptual representational content. The first task undertaken is to argue that a representationalist account of the content of perceptual experience is required. The strategy employed is to both criticize and dismiss competing positions, particularly sense-datum theories, and build a positive case on behalf of representationalism by focusing on the transparency of experience and the connection between perceptual experience and belief. It is then demonstrated that representationalist accounts that take the content of perceptual experience to be propositional in nature are inadequate because they cannot accommodate the rich detail included in the representational content of experience. John McDowell's claim that our capacity for demonstrative thought provides us with the resources required to conceptually capture the fine-grained features presented in experience is also examined and rejected. Acceptance of the idea that perceptual experience includes a nonconceptual form of representation is motivated by arguing that not only does it offer a means of accounting for the fine-grained features represented in perceptual experience, but that it also provides a way of fixing the possession conditions for a basic and important group of concepts. A statement of how the nonconceptual representational content of experience is to be specified is also presented, and an account of the mental representation of the nonconceptual representational content of perceptual experience is included. The dissertation concludes with an argument for the claim that perceptual experiences with nonconceptual representational contents can be legitimately attributed only to creatures having at least a minimally sophisticated mental life, which includes a self-concept and a conception of the objective world.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,836

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Does Perceptual Content Have to Be Objective? A Defence of Nonconceptualism.Eva Schmidt - 2015 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 46 (1):201-214.
Qualitative character and sensory representation.Douglas B. Meehan - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (4):630-641.
Perception, generality, and reasons.Hannah Ginsborg - 2011 - In Andrew Reisner & Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen, Reasons for Belief. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 131--57.
Nonconceptual content and the sound of music.Michael Luntley - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):402-426.
The Relational and Representational Character of Perceptual Experience.Susanna Schellenberg - 2014 - In Berit Brogaard, Does Perception Have Content? New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 199-219.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-05

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Wayne Wright
California State University, Long Beach

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references