Color qualities and reference to them

Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2 (December):145-169 (1972)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Rightly or, wrongly I am going to take it that the doctrine of simple qualities says three things. First, that yellow, for example, is a simple unanalyzable quality. I don’t really believe this to be true, except in what it denies, but I have no immediate quarrel with it. Second, a simple quality, such as yellow, is what it is quite independently of its pattern of exemplification. Third, yellow is somehow ineffable, the sheer dazzling yellowishness of yellow things cannot be conveyed in words. In the third case, I do not mean the commonplace that words are different from things, that the word ‘yellow’ is not itself yellow. I mean the view that there is something about color qualities as immediately apprehended by us that eludes description. Now all these views are somewhat old-fashioned. The third is hardly mentioned nowadays. Yet I am not so sure that we are not still very much in their grip. In any case, philosophical hemlil)eS oscillate almost as frequently as do those of high fashion so it should not surprise anyone if these views were to come back into vogue, especially if phenomenology becomes important in this country. Now it may be more a matter of convenience than of historical accuracy that I am lumping these three doctrines together as “the doctrine of simple qualities”. Perhaps “doctrine of atomistic qualities” would be better. I am reasonably certain that the second and third doctrines mutually entail each other, although it has to be conceded that the situation is fairly complicated. I shall have something to say about the third doctrine–the doctrine of ineffability, but I shall be mostly concerned to refute the second doctrine–the doctrine that the identity of a quality is independent of its extension–and to put something else in its place. I shall be concerned incidentally to examine certain puzzling statements like ‘Red is a color’, ‘Red is between orange and purple’ and ‘Whatever is green is extended’, which seem to be necessary but don’t seem to be analytic.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,902

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Divine Simplicity.William E. Mann - 1982 - Religious Studies 18 (4):451 - 471.
Simplicity and Properties: A Reply to Morris.William E. Mann - 1986 - Religious Studies 22 (3-4):343 - 353.
Content, character, and color.Sydney Shoemaker - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):253-78.
Simple colours.Nicholas Nathan - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (July):345-353.
Intentionality and Privacy.C. W. Webb - 1987 - Idealistic Studies 17 (2):97-107.
Substances without Substrata.N. L. Wilson - 1959 - Review of Metaphysics 12 (4):521-539.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
23 (#932,407)

6 months
6 (#838,367)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Propositions for Semantics and Propositions for Epistemology.N. L. Wilson - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):375 - 399.
The Two Main Problems of Philosophy.N. L. Wilson - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (2):199-216.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Mind and the World-Order.Hugh Miller - 1931 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 38 (2):11-12.
The last word on being red and blue all over.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1954 - Philosophical Studies 5 (1):5-10.
Mr. Aldrich's “Last Word”.David S. Shwayder - 1954 - Philosophical Studies 5 (4):62-64.

Add more references