Do Doctors Have a Responsibility to Challenge the Distorting Influence of Commerce on Healthcare Delivery? The Case of Assisted Reproductive Technology

Health Care Analysis:1-13 (forthcoming)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Medicine has always existed in a marketplace, and there have been extensive discussions about the ethical implications of commerce in health care. For the most part, this discussion has focused on health professionals’ interactions with pharmaceutical and other health technology industries, with less attention given to other types of commercial influences, such as corporatized health services and fee-for-service practice. This is a significant lacuna because in many jurisdictions, some or all of healthcare is delivered in the private sector. Using the exemplar of Assisted Reproductive Technologies (ART), this paper asks: what, if any, responsibilities do doctors have to challenge the distorting influence of commerce in healthcare, other than those arising from their own interactions with health technology companies? ART provides a good focus for this question because it is an area of practice that has historically been provided in the private sector. First, we describe a range of concepts that offer helpful heuristics for capturing how and when doctors can reasonably be said to have responsibilities to resist commercial distortion, including: complicity, acquiescence, wilful ignorance, non-wilful ignorance, and duplicity. Second, we present ways that individual doctors can act to stop questionable behaviour on the part of their colleagues, clinics/corporations, and their profession. Third, we note that there are many situations where change cannot be achieved by individuals acting alone, and so we consider the responsibilities of health professionals as collectives as well as the role that professional bodies and regulators should play.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,394

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Physician, heal thyself: Do doctors have a responsibility to practise self-care?Joshua Parker & Ben Davies - 2024 - In Ben Davies, Gabriel De Marco, Neil Levy & Julian Savulescu (eds.), Responsibility and Healthcare. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 247-268.
Confidentiality in Prison Health care – A Practical Guide.Bernice Elger & David Shaw - 2018 - In Bernice S. Elger, Catherine Ritter & Heino Stöver (eds.), Emerging Issues in Prison Health. Springer.
Do we still need doctors?John D. Lantos - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
Smokers' rights to health care.R. Persaud - 1995 - Journal of Medical Ethics 21 (5):281-287.
Setting Expectations for the Federal Role in Public Health Emergencies.Eric D. Hargan - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (s1):8-12.

Analytics

Added to PP
2024-11-19

Downloads
1 (#1,945,123)

6 months
1 (#1,887,784)

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Ainsley Newson
University of Sydney

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Individual Complicity: The Tortured Patient.Chiara Lepora - 2013 - In On complicity and compromise. Oxford United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Climate Change and Structural Emissions.Monica Aufrecht - 2011 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (2):201-213.
Healthcare and complicity in Australian immigration detention.Ryan Essex - 2016 - Monash Bioethics Review 34 (2):136-147.

Add more references