Reply to Critics

Philosophical Studies 128 (3):711-738 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Linsky’s central point is correct; Kripke’s distinction between rigid and nonrigid designators can be extended in a straightforward way from singular terms to general terms. In both cases, for an expression to rigidly designate its extension is for it to designate the same extension with respect to every possible world-state (in which it has an extension at all). On this account, simple natural kind terms like water, gold, electricity, blue, and tiger – as well as ordinary general terms like bachelor, philosopher, automobile and triangle – designate the same extension with respect to each world-state. As I see it, however, the two differ importantly in the metaphysics of their designata. Whereas a term like bachelor designates a property that may be distinguished from other properties that are necessarily coextensive with it, natural kinds differ from one another only if there are possible world-states in which some of their instances are different. Intuitively this seems plausible; it is hard to imagine two distinct species of animal, two distinct substances, or two distinct colors which have precisely the same instances in every possible world-state. This is important for my linguistic model. Consider, for example, the color blue (which I take to be a natural kind). Color science tells us that the object-color blue is determined..

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,795

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Are General Terms Rigid?Nathan Salmon - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (1):117 - 134.
Rigid Application.Michael Devitt - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 125 (2):139-165.
Reply to Critics.Naoko Saito - 2022 - The Pluralist 17 (1):119-124.
A simple theory of rigidity.Tristan Grøtvedt Haze - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 178 (12):4187-4199.
Necessity and rigidly designating kind terms.Ben S. Cordry - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 119 (3):243-264.
Reply to critics.Peter Vanderschraaf - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (5):1741-1756.
Reply to Critics.Natalia I. Kuznetsova - 2024 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 61 (1):72-74.
Reply to Critics.Tatiana D. Sokolova - 2023 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 60 (2):72-74.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
144 (#157,032)

6 months
19 (#157,171)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Scott Soames
University of Southern California

Citations of this work

Rigid designators.Joseph LaPorte - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Are natural kind terms special?Åsa Wikforss - 2010 - In Helen Beebee & Nigel Sabbarton-Leary (eds.), The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds. New York: Routledge.
A pragmatic defense of Millianism.Arvid Båve - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 138 (2):271 - 289.

View all 18 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references