Morgan’s Minimalism: An Epistemic Approach to Contract Law

Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 28 (3-4):356-379 (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

ABSTRACTLawyers tend to fall into two categories. Some argue that the law should reflect our moral duties to each other. Seen that way, law is a form of applied ethics, and the social sciences should play only a very limited role in the reasoning of legal scholars. Others argue that the law should be developed consistently with the conclusions of social science, arguing, for example, that the task of the law is to maximize economic efficiency, such that law must conform to economists’ conclusions about which rules are the most efficient. Jonathan Morgan rejects both of those approaches. He does not think that the law should mimic our moral duties, but he is also skeptical about the utility of social sciences in predicting the effects of law. He also argues that courts are not institutionally competent to deal with social-science evidence. However, he does not conclude that the social sciences must be rejected by legal scholarship. He himself uses them to establish that law is generally not needed to govern ongoing commercial relationships, that it is required only when such relationships break down, and that courts should focus on resolving such breakdowns as simply and predictably as possible. Based on those considerations, he sketches a minimalist vision of contract law and argues that it is the best we can hope for.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,190

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Self-certification and the Moral Aims of the Law.Arthur Ripstein - 2012 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 25 (1):201-217.
Morals and Interpretation: A Path to Dworkin's Jurisprudence.Chinedu Januarius Onyebadi - 2001 - Dissertation, Universite Catholique de Louvain (Belgium)
The morality of law and economics.Russell Hardin - 1992 - Law and Philosophy 11 (4):331 - 384.
Three separation theses.James Morauta - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (2):111-135.
Jurisprudence and Necessity.Danny Priel - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 20 (1):173-200.
Trust and Fiduciary Law.Matthew Harding - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (1):81-102.
Language and Law: Brevity and Drafting in Law, Business, and the Social Sciences.Joseph Shattah - 2019 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 58 (1):155-171.
Risks and wrongs.Jules L. Coleman - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-11-14

Downloads
9 (#1,558,489)

6 months
3 (#1,066,589)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Freedom has no intrinsic value: Liberalism and voluntarism.Jeffrey Friedman - 2013 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 25 (1):38-85.
Absolute Freedom of Contract: Grotian Lessons for Libertarians.Jeppe von Platz - 2013 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 25 (1):107-119.
“Law, Liberty and Morality”: Fifty Years On. [REVIEW]Massimo Renzo - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (3):417-418.

Add more references