Human Freedom and the Philosophical Attitude

Educational Philosophy and Theory 47 (11):1185-1197 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Attempts to describe the essential features of the Western philosophical tradition can often be characterized as ‘boundary work’, that is, the attempt to create, promote, attack, or reinforce specific notions of the ‘philosophical’ in order to demarcate it as a field of intellectual inquiry. During the last century, the dominant tendency has been to delineate the discipline in terms of formal methods, techniques, and concepts and a given set of standard problems and alternative available solutions. One vital feature of the philosophical tradition that has played a certain rather subterranean but nonetheless indispensable role, which I will discuss in this article, is that of repeatedly and stringently calling into question the conditions of its own possibility. The Cartesian tradition shares with the anti-philosophers the insight that this questioning itself is and has always been a problem, perhaps the deepest problem, for philosophy. The idea that one has the right, even the responsibility, to pose questions that are non-standard, not comme il faut, perhaps even taboo, lay at the very heart of notions such as ‘the pursuit of truth’, ‘vita contemplativa’, and ‘philosophy as work on oneself’. On what grounds can one possibly assert such a right? In the Western tradition, it has most often been associated with a form of genuine doubt founded in deep engagement with some subject matter, i.e. the notion that one has a ‘problem’ demanding that one take responsibility for one’s beliefs and thoughts, both morally and logically. It seems to me that the meaning of this most basic attitude is something that each generation must rediscover for itself; indeed, recreate for itself in a new environment and under new conditions. Thus, the blindness of the past, in this self-understanding of philosophy, need not bind or blind us in the future. To the contrary, the European intellectual tradition can be seen as providing a series of perspicuous representations of intermittently faltering and flourishing attempts at asserting the viability of the idea of human freedom as essentially bound up with the pursuit of truth. As such, it is of necessity open to perpetual revision.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,505

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Insight: The Process, Boundaries and Development.Wen-Hsiang Chen - 2006 - Philosophy and Culture 33 (11):109-125.
Wittgenstein’s Critique of Metaphysics in the Tractatus.Thomas A. Fay - 1971 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 20:51-61.
Reason and World: Between Tradition and Another Beginning.Werner Marx - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
Language analysis and metaphysical inquiry.Irving M. Copilowish - 1949 - Philosophy of Science 16 (1):65-70.
Analyticity and conceptual truth.Paul A. Boghossian - 1994 - Philosophical Issues 5:117-131.
Reply to professor Bergmann.Irving M. Copilowish - 1949 - Philosophy of Science 16 (1):74.
Sankara, Śāntarakṣita and Spinoza.Tammy Nyden - 2012 - In Marie-Louise Friquegnon & Noé Dinnerstein (eds.), Studies on Śāntarakṣita’s Yogācāra Madhyamaka. Global Scholarly Publications.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-09-03

Downloads
44 (#507,227)

6 months
10 (#413,587)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Sharon Rider
Uppsala Universitet

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Critique of Pure Reason.I. Kant - 1787/1998 - Philosophy 59 (230):555-557.
An autobiography.Robin George Collingwood - 1939 - New York, etc.]: Oxford University Press.
An Autobiography.R. G. Collingwood - 1941 - Ethics 51 (3):369-370.
An Autobiography.R. G. Collingwood - 1940 - Philosophy 15 (57):89-91.
Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind.Robert B. Pippin - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):449 - 475.

View all 8 references / Add more references