A bad argument for good reasons

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (1):69 – 73 (1993)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

1. In general we agree to recognize the existence, if not the methodological fertility or epistemological legitimacy, of a "rationalist model," at least when we refer to what economists do when they offer explanations.1 However two remarks must be made about this. First, it must be emphasized that this model is not unique, but generic: in fact, it is more a family of models of which the fundamental theoretical suppositions are susceptible to large variations. There are here, as it were, several possible axiomatic bases. One formulation is, for example and to use von Mises's term, praxeological (axed on means/end relation). Another emphasizes the preference/constraint relation (Harsanyi). Other contrasting models are those putting forward the maximization of expected utility (von Neumann-Morgenstern) and those making the satisficing hypothesis (Simon). Second, however, it must also be said that philosophers of science do not really agree on what is asserted by the "principle of rationality" or on what is its status. For example, Popper (1982) made it a minimal empirical hypothesis, or practically empty, and denied, furthermore, that it was a universally valid psychological law. Hempel (1965) did not hesitate, in contrast, to make it a law of experimental psychology which would play an implicit or explicit role in any adequate and complete explanation of behaviour or action in social sciences or history. Dray, to cite another classic author (cf. Dray 1957), made this principle the base for the explanations of historians, but denied it the status of a nomological proposition. In consequence, it is difficult to proceed as if there were a theoretical consensus among researchers when they base their explanatory arguments on the rationality of agents. This is clearly not the case. However, Raymond Boudon is right to consider the "rationalist model" an extension to all the social sciences of the model of explanation which is found at the base of what has been called the "marginalist revolution" in economics..

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,830

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Explaining Explanations in AI.Brent Mittelstadt - forthcoming - FAT* 2019 Proceedings 1.
Models and Explanation.Alisa Bokulich - 2017 - In Magnani Lorenzo & Bertolotti Tommaso Wayne (eds.), Springer Handbook of Model-Based Science. Springer. pp. 103-118.
Reasons and advice for the practically rational.Robert Neal Johnson - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (3):619-625.
What is psychological explanation?William Bechtel & Cory Wright - 2009 - In Sarah Robins, John Symons & Paco Calvo (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 113--130.
Contextualism.Claudia Bianchi - 2010 - Handbook of Pragmatics Online.
Abduction and Hypothesis Withdrawal in Science.Lorenzo Magnani - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 37:180-187.
Do statistical laws have explanatory efficacy?Samuel E. Gluck - 1955 - Philosophy of Science 22 (1):34-38.
The Universalizability of Moral Judgements.Peter Winch - 1965 - The Monist 49 (2):196-214.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
66 (#317,852)

6 months
6 (#838,367)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Robert Nadeau
Université du Québec à Montreal

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Laws and Explanations in History.W. H. Dray - 1957 - Philosophy 34 (129):170-172.
The Explanation of Behavior.W. D. Joske - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27 (1):135-137.

Add more references