Opposites From Hesiod to Aristotle: Greek Patterns of Description and Inference

Dissertation, Vanderbilt University (1990)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Throughout the classical period opposition is an increasingly important element of aetiological descriptions and of procedures for regulating inference. Contrary to Lloyd and to structuralist critics, archaic Greek thought is not oppositionally structured. Hesiod's Theogony, in particular, is not oppositionally structured. ;Anaximander is the first of the Ionians to employ a set of opposites, genesis and phthora, in aetiological description. Anaximenes employs a set of opposites, puknosis and araiosis, which describe a continuum on which there are an infinite number of possible physical states. Heracleitus removes his logos from allegiance to any particular set of physical predicates by making the conflict of opposites itself the fundamental principle of the cosmos. ;The identity of opposites which Heracleitus asserts is the problem which motivates the establishment of the conceptual categories which those opposites constitute, but the fragments of Heracleitus do not constitute a logic. ;Parmenides' poem contains both necessary rules for inference, , and, in the path of Truth, the image of an ontology, conceived as a realm on which opposites do not impinge. ;Early Plato follows a double path reminiscent of Parmenides. Particulars are subject to change; forms are unchanging. Particulars receive opposites; forms do not. Forms have opposites; particulars do not. As with Parmenidean scholarship, Platonic scholarship has been confused by the notion that Plato thought any term could be an opposite. This view is a projection of modern logical assumptions which Plato does not share. ;In Aristotle there is not one fourfold classification of opposites but a more adaptive scheme in which Aristotle recognizes different conceptions of opposition as privileged or advantaged with respect to tasks of differentiation in ontology, logic, and epistemology. Logical opposites are fundamental to Aristotelian undertakings in aetiological description and inference. Privation is primary in the former; contradiction in the latter. The traditional classification is most useful in ontology and dialectic

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,060

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Opposites and Plato's Principle of Change in the Phaedo Cyclical Argument.Gale Justin - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (3):423-448.
Nietzsche’s Denial of Opposites.Steven D. Weiss - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:261-305.
Plato on False Judgment in the Theaetetus.Axel Barceló-Aspeitia & Edgar González-Varela - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (3):349-372.
On the Identity of Opposites.Kuan Feng - 1971 - Contemporary Chinese Thought 3 (2):130-146.
The Implicit Logic of Hesiod's Cosmogony.Mitchell Miller - 1983 - Independent Journal of Philosophy:131-142.
Phusis, Opposites and Ontological Dependence in Heraclitus.Richard Neels - 2018 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 35 (3):199-217.
Dialectic and Negation.Otis Lee - 1947 - Review of Metaphysics 1 (1):3 - 23.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-06

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references