Pragmatic Ethics

In Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory. Malden, Mass., USA: Blackwell. pp. 400--419 (1999)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Pragmatism is a philosophical movement developed near the turn of the century in the of several prominent American philosophers, most notably, Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Although many contemporary analytic philosophers never studied American Philosophy in graduate schoo l, analytic philosophy has been significantly shaped by philosophers strongly influenced by that tradition, most especially W. V. Quine, Donald Davidson, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Rorty. Like other philosophical movements, it developed in response to the then-dominant philosophical wisdom. What unified pragmatism was its rejection of certain epistemological assumptions about the nature of truth, objectivity, and rationality. The rejection of these assumptions springs from the pragmatist's belief that practice is primary in philosophy. Meaningful inquiry originates in practice. Theorizing is valuable, for sure, but its value arises practice, is informed by practice, and, its proper aim is to clarify, coordinate, and inform practice. Theorizing divorced practice is useless. Pragmatism is at once both familiar and radical. Familiar in that it often begins with rather ordinary views; radical in that it often sees in those views insights that philosophers and lay people miss or misunderstand. A pragmatic ethic employs criteria without being criterial. It is objective without being absolutist. It acknowledges that ethical judgements are relative, without being relativistic. And it tolerates - indeed, welcomes some moral differences, without being irresolute. Precisely what each of these means, and why pragmatists hold them, emerges throughout this paper. I begin with the first since it sets the stage for introducing other pivotal pragmatic ideas. Ethical theorizing begins when we think about how we ought to live. Many people assume that means we must look for moral criteria: some list of rules or principles whereby we can distinguish good from bad and right wrong, or a list of virtues we try to inculcate..

Other Versions

original LaFollette, Hugh (1999) "Pragmatic ethics". In LaFollette, Hugh, Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, pp. 400--419: Blackwell (1999)

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,854

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

What Is and What Should Pragmatic Ethics Be?Juan Pablo Serra - 2010 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 2 (2):101-114.
The pragmatic turn.Richard J. Bernstein - 2010 - Malden, MA: Polity Press.
Disentangling Facts and Values: an Analysis of Putnam’s Pragmatic Ethics.Darlei Dall’Agnol - 2013 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 17 (2):265.
The Disunity of Pragmatism.Paul Forster - 2018 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 7:143-157.
Pragmatism in professional practice.Richard John Ormerod - 2021 - Systems Research and Behavioral Science 38 (6):797-816.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
52 (#423,578)

6 months
1 (#1,894,012)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Hugh LaFollette
University of South Florida

Citations of this work

Living on a Slippery Slope.Hugh LaFollette - 2005 - The Journal of Ethics 9 (3-4):475-499.
Toward an Epistemology of the Hand.Svend Brinkmann & Lene Tanggaard - 2009 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 29 (3):243-257.
Agrarian philosophy and ecological ethics.Paul B. Thompson - 2008 - Science and Engineering Ethics 14 (4):527-544.
Mind-Independent Values Don’t Exist, But Moral Truth Does.Maarten Van Doorn - 2017 - Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism ; Vol 25, No 1 25 (1):5-24.

View all 11 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The truth in ethical relativism.Hugh LaFollette - 1991 - Journal of Social Philosophy 22 (1):146-154.

Add more references