Self-Determination and International Order

The Monist 89 (2):356-370 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Towards the end of the first world war, a “principle of self-determination” was proposed as a foundation for international order. In the words of its chief advocate, U.S. President Woodrow Wilson, it specified that the “settlement of every question, whether of territory, of sovereignty, of economic arrangement, or of political relationship” is to be made “upon the basis of the free acceptance of that settlement by the people immediately concerned and not upon the basis of the material interest or advantage of any other nation or people which may desire a different settlement for sake of its own exterior influence or mastery” (Wilson 1927, 233). The principle played a significant role in deliberations about lands newly liberated by the first world war, and, in the aftermath of the second, it was enshrined within Article 1 of the United Nations Charter which called upon member nations “to develop friendly relations among nations based on respect for the principle of equal rights and self-determination of peoples.” Its status within international law was further heightened by the 1966 Covenants on Civil and Political Rights and on Economic Social and Cultural Rights, whose first articles specify the following: “All peoples have the right of self-determination. By virtue of that right they freely determine their political status and freely pursue their economic, social, and cultural development.” In 1970, General Assembly Resolution 2625 added that, “every state has the duty to respect this right in accordance with the provision of the Charter.”.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,945

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A Critique of National Self-Determination.Omar Hussein Dahbour - 1995 - Dissertation, City University of New York
Changes in the U.S. Aboriginal Policy in the 1960s – 1970s.O. Kozachuk - 2014 - Epistemological studies in Philosophy, Social and Political Sciences 2 (24):147-153.
Group-differentiated rights for Indigenous communities that straddle borders.Michael Luoma - 2025 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 28 (1):121-142.
The Right to Self-determination of Nigeria’s Niger Delta.Mark Omorovie Ikeke - 2018 - Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy (Philippine e-journal) 19 (1):53-65.
Human Rights.Charles R. Beitz - 1996 - In Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit & Thomas Winfried Menko Pogge, A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 628–637.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
168 (#145,161)

6 months
11 (#316,199)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tomis Kapitan
Indiana University, Bloomington (PhD)

Citations of this work

Add more citations

References found in this work

On Nationality.David Miller - 1995 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Liberal Nationalism.Yael Tamir - 1995 - Princeton University Press.
Liberal Nationalism.Yael Tamir - 1993 - Ethics 105 (3):626-645.
National self-determination.Avishai Margalit & Joseph Raz - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (9):439-461.
The Idea of a Legitimate State.David Copp - 1999 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1):3-45.

View all 13 references / Add more references