Sinking Cohen's Flagship — or Why People with Expensive Tastes Should not be Compensated

Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (4):341-354 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

G. A. Cohen argues that egalitarians should compensate for expensive tastes or for the fact that they are expensive. Ronald Dworkin, by contrast, regards most expensive tastes as unworthy of compensation — only if a person disidentifies with his own such tastes (i.e. wishes he did not have them) is compensation appropriate. Dworkinians appeal, inter alia, to the so-called ‘first-person’ or ‘continuity’ test. According to the continuity test, an appropriate standard of interpersonal comparison reflects people's own assessment of their relative standing: Person A can only legitimately demand compensation from person B if he regards himself as worse off, all things considered, than B. The typical bearer of expensive tastes does not regard herself as being worse off than others with less expensive tastes. Hence, in the typical case, pace Cohen, compensation for expensive tastes is inappropriate. The article scrutinizes this rationale for not compensating for expensive tastes. Especially, we try to bolster the continuity test by relating it to Dworkin's distinction between integrated and detached values, pointing out that an argument for the continuity test can be built on the assumption that equality has integrated value. In brief, the point is that a metric of equality should be assessed, partly, in virtue of its consequences for related ideals. One of these is the kind of justificatory community promoted by the continuity test. We defend this view against an objection to the effect that equality is a detached value. We conclude that the continuity test constitutes a strong foothold for the resourcist egalitarian reluctance to compensate people for their expensive tastes

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 104,804

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Welfare Luck Egalitarianism and Expensive Tastes.Nils Holtug - 2015 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 2 (1):179-206.
Egalitarian Justice and Valuational Judgment.Carl Knight - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (4):482-498.
Externalism, expensive tastes, and equality.Keith Dowding - 2007 - In Barbara Montero & Mark D. White, Economics and the mind. New York: Routledge.
Mistakes and the continuity test.Hugh Lazenby - 2016 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 15 (2):190-205.
Expensive Tastes and Distributive Justice.Simon Keller - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (4):529-552.
Justice as Fairness: Luck Egalitarian, Not Rawlsian.Michael Otsuka - 2010 - The Journal of Ethics 14 (3-4):217-230.
Choosing expensive tastes.Louis Kaplow - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (3):415-425.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-08-18

Downloads
117 (#193,976)

6 months
21 (#147,710)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Rasmus Hansen
Copenhagen Business School
Soren Flinch Midtgaard
Aarhus University

Citations of this work

Mistakes and the continuity test.Hugh Lazenby - 2016 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 15 (2):190-205.
Desert, Bell Motion, and Fairness.Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3):639-655.
Liberal equality: political not erinaceous.Matthew Clayton - 2016 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (4):416-433.

View all 8 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references