Stanley Cavell on What We Say

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 9 (9) (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In his early essay, “Must We Mean What We Say”, Cavell argues that the claims of ordinary language philosophers regarding “what we say when” are not empirical generalizations about a given group of speakers but are rather to be understood as measuring the limits of what counts as a coherent act of thinking and speaking. Cavell’s charge against the skeptic about the external world is that he seeks to think and speak beyond these limits. In this paper I compare Cavell’s response to the skeptic to Davidson’s. Both base their responses on a broadly Kantian approach that appeals to the conditions under which thinking or speaking about objects is possible. On this approach the skeptic isn’t giving a false answer to an intelligible question, but rather, the question to which the skeptic is giving an answer is shown to be in some way unintelligible. But while Davidson’s critique of the skeptic is based on the conditions of ascribing meaning to one’s words, and contents to one’s beliefs, Cavell’s critique is based on the failure of the skeptic to mean the words he uses in the way that he needs. This difference expresses an underlying disagreement about the meaning of “meaning”: for Davidson the world comes into view through the meaning of our words and concepts, through the contents of our beliefs; for Cavell, the world comes into view through the agreement in “criteria” that are a condition of applying words and concepts to the world. This difference illuminates what Cavell calls “the truth of skepticism”: the idea that “my relation to the world and to others in general is not one of knowing”.

Other Versions

No versions found

Similar books and articles

Stanley Cavell’s Argument of the Ordinary.Avner Baz - 2018 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 7 (2):9-48.
Cavell, Skepticism, and the Ordinary Mind.Eric Joseph Ritter - 2019 - Dissertation, Vanderbilt University
Cavell’s Method.Sandra Laugier - 2021 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 9 (9).
Stanley Cavell.Amanda Fulford - 2018 - In Paul Smeyers (ed.), International Handbook of Philosophy of Education. Springer. pp. 81-90.
Davidson's Epistemology.Ernest Sosa - 2003 - In Kirk Ludwig (ed.), Contemporary Philosophy in Focus: Donald Davidson. Cambridge University Press.
No Picnic: Cavell on Rule‐Descriptions.Constantine Sandis - 2021 - Philosophical Investigations 44 (3):295-317.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-11-07

Downloads
386 (#74,499)

6 months
161 (#25,217)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Arata Hamawaki
Auburn University

References found in this work

The significance of philosophical scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Wittgenstein on rules and private language.Saul Kripke - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (4):496-499.
Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language.John Searle - 1969 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 4 (1):59-61.

View all 13 references / Add more references