Perfect pitch and Austinian examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein, and the philosophical significance of ordinary language

Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 48 (4):356 – 389 (2005)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In Cavell (1994), the ability to follow and produce Austinian examples of ordinary language use is compared with the faculty of perfect pitch. Exploring this comparison, I clarify a number of central and interrelated aspects of Cavell's philosophy: (1) his way of understanding Wittgenstein's vision of language, and in particular his claim that this vision is "terrifying," (2) the import of Wittgenstein's vision for Cavell's conception of the method of ordinary language philosophy, (3) Cavell's dissatisfaction with Austin, and in particular his claim that Austin is not clear about the nature and possible achievements of his own philosophical procedures, and (4) Cavell's notion that the temptation of skepticism is perennial and incurable. Cavell's reading of Wittgenstein is related to that of John McDowell. Like McDowell, Cavell takes Wittgenstein to be saying that the traditional attempt to justify our practices from an external standpoint is misguided, since such detachment involves losing sight of those conceptual and perceptual capacities in terms of which a practice is understood by its engaged participants. Unlike McDowell, however, Cavell consistently rejects the idea that philosophical clearsightedness can or should free us from that fear of groundlessness which motivates the traditional search for external justification.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,225

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Stanley Cavell’s Argument of the Ordinary.Avner Baz - 2018 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 7 (2):9-48.
Cavell and the Quest for a Voice.Sofia Miguens - 2021 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 9 (9).
Contending with Stanley Cavell.Stanley Cavell & Russell B. Goodman (eds.) - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Logic and Voice.Espen Hammer - 2021 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 9 (9).
Cavell's 'Must We Mean What We Say' at 50.Greg Chase, Juliet Floyd & Sandra Laugier (eds.) - 2022 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
124 (#175,398)

6 months
9 (#482,469)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Martin Gustafsson
Åbo Akademi University

Citations of this work

Contemporary ordinary language philosophy.Nat Hansen - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (8):556-569.
Must we measure what we mean?Nat Hansen - 2017 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 60 (8):785-815.
The ordinary and the experimental: Cook Wilson and Austin on method in philosophy.Guy Longworth - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (5):939-960.
Ourselves in translation: Stanley Cavell and philosophy as autobiography.Naoko Saito - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (2):253-267.

View all 9 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1956 - Oxford: Macmillan. Edited by G. E. M. Anscombe, Rush Rhees & G. H. von Wright.
Mind and World.John McDowell - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):99-109.
Mind, Value, and Reality.John Henry McDowell - 1998 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Mind and World.John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):389-394.

View all 19 references / Add more references