The Need for Quinean Pragmatism in the Theory of History

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 8 (2) (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

I present the history of philosophy, and history more generally, as a context of ideas, with respect to which philosophers and historians share concerns about the meaning of the texts they both use, and where for some there is a principled contrast between seeing meaning in quasi-mathematical terms (“a philosophical stance”) or in terms of context (“a historical stance”). I introduce this imagined (but not imaginary) world of ideas as temporally extended. Returning to my early research into the epistemic problems of historiography, I present my view that foundational was meaningful language in a shared world, and I display some difficulties found in handling the “wholeness” of historical accounts. I came to realise that it was epistemic opposition between historical accounts that mattered. I concluded that analytical philosophy was wrong to assume that individual sentences were free-standing meaningful units that could be juxtaposed with others at whim, and that an understanding of the rational grounds for determining relevance was needed. In order to make sense of this I used Quine’s conception of the “web of belief,” and noted that a historical account could be treated as a “unit of empirical significance” in his terms. I observe that, although the epistemic problems of history arose for me before I considered his pragmatic position, nevertheless attention to those problems required me to adopt the Quine-based form of pragmatism I describe. I came to realise that I had wrongly adopted a synchronic view of the Quinean web, thereby adopting a “philosophical stance.” Rather, the web should be conceived in diachronic terms as a rolling web, so forming history itself. It is wrong to think that language started in atomistic terms so that, following Aristotle, it first consisted of simple concepts forming sentences of brief and narrow subject-predicate form. Instead, early communications took the form of oral traditions usually in narrative form. Meaningful wholes such as historical accounts are conceptually prior to atomistic sentences and need to be seen in extended temporal terms, so that an Aristotelian subject-predicate metaphysics is implausible. Quine’s pragmatism framed and facilitated my historical stance despite the unashamed philosophical stance that he adopted.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,667

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Traditions in Philosophy of History.Jonathan Gorman - 2018 - Maynooth Philosophical Papers 9:59-79.
Truth and Historicity: A Study of Bernard Lonergan's Account of Doctrine.John Francis Wallenhorst - 1990 - Dissertation, University of St. Michael's College (Canada)
Truth's fabric.Wolfram Hinzen - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (2):194–219.
The tribunal of philosophy and its norms: history and philosophy in Georges Canguilhem’s historical epistemology.Cristina Chimisso - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 34 (2):297-327.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-03-26

Downloads
47 (#473,047)

6 months
15 (#212,687)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Jonathan L. Gorman
Queen's University, Belfast

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
Individuals.P. F. Strawson - 1959 - Garden City, N.Y.: Routledge.
Individuals.P. F. Strawson - 1959 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 14 (2):246-246.
Consequences of Pragmatism.Richard Rorty - 1984 - Erkenntnis 21 (3):423-431.

View all 21 references / Add more references