Defining Art and Artworlds

Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):375-384 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Most art is made by people with a well-developed concept of art and who are familiar with its forms and genres as well as with the informal institutions of its presentation and reception. This is reflected in philosophers’ proposed definitions. The earliest artworks were made by people who lacked the concept and in a context that does not resemble the art traditions of established societies, however. An adequate definition must accommodate their efforts. The result is a complex, hybrid definition: something is art (a) if it shows excellence of skill and achievement in realizing significant aesthetic goals, and either doing so is its primary, identifying function or doing so makes a vital contribution to the realization of its primary, identifying function, or (b) if it falls under an art genre or art form established and publicly recognized within an art tradition, or (c) if it is intended by its maker/presenter to be art and its maker/presenter does what is necessary and appropriate to realizing that intention. Meanwhile, artworlds—historically developed traditions of works, genres, theories, criticism, conventions for presentation, and so on—play a crucial but implicit role in (b) and (c). They are to be characterized in terms of their origins.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,173

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Art by Proxy.Robert Yanal - 2023 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 81 (3):341-347.
Philosophical perspectives on art.Stephen Davies - 2007 - New York;: Oxford University Press.
The Japanese Tea Ceremony and Pancultural Definitions of Art.Daniel Wilson - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (1):33-44.
The Aesthetic Function of Art.Gary Iseminger - 1999 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 4:169-176.
Coevolutionary aesthetics in human and biotic artworlds.Richard O. Prum - 2013 - Biology and Philosophy 28 (5):811-832.
The aesthetic essence of art.Richard Lind - 1992 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (2):117-129.
Contextualized Functions: Possible Tensions In Stecker’s Definition.Matthew Rowe - 2007 - Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics 4 (1):18-27.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-10-27

Downloads
153 (#149,313)

6 months
12 (#290,681)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

The definition of art.Thomas Adajian - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Practice-Centered Pluralism and a Disjunctive Theory of Art.Caleb Hazelwood - 2021 - British Journal of Aesthetics 61 (2):213-227.
Art: Brought to You by Creative Machines.Steffen Steinert - 2017 - Philosophy and Technology 30 (3):267-284.
Are Some Perfumes Works of Art?Brozzo.Chiara Brozzo - 2020 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 78 (1):21-32.
Creativity as an Artistic Merit.James Grant - 2018 - In Berys Nigel Gaut & Matthew Kieran (eds.), Creativity and Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 333-349.

View all 11 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Defining art historically.Jerrold Levinson - 1979 - British Journal of Aesthetics 19 (3):21-33.
Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value.Robert Stecker - 1997 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (3):311-313.
Refining art historically.Jerrold Levinson - 1989 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (1):21-33.
The problem of non-perceptual art.James Shelley - 2003 - British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (4):363-378.

View all 24 references / Add more references