Sovereignty: Ancient and Modern

Polis 17 (1-2):2-34 (2000)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Though the notion of the free, or self-governed community, originated in ancient Greece, the Greek polis seems to pose a problem for the modern post-Hobbesian concept of sovereignty. For the latter presupposes that of the State, that is an agency which monopolizes the use of violence, as an instrument by which sovereignty is constituted. Yet, the polis was not a State but rather what the anthropologists call a stateless community. The latter is characterized by the absence of ‘government’, that is of an agency which has separated itself from the rest of social life and which monopolizes the use of violence. In stateless societies the ability to use force is more or less evenly distributed among armed or potentially armed members of the community. Being stateless, then, in what sense can we say that the polis was sovereign? On the practical level the Greek polis had a very limited ability to control and direct legislation. The decentralised nature of Greek society and the absence of coercive apparatuses meant that the laws had to be identical with the customs of the community or else that decisions had to be shared by a wide consensus, which imposed a severe limitation on the ability of the poleis to change their laws or initiate changes in the community. On the theoretical level, the absence of a State was complementary to the absence of the notion of sovereign, whether it is a person or an institution or a body which was above the law and a source of the law. Thus Greek ‘republicanism’ was different from the modern one in as much as it did not have the notion of ‘the people’ as a constituting element and Greek ‘rule of law’ lacked the modern notion of a positive open legislation

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,388

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Hobbes and the ‘Greek tongues’.M. Berent - 1996 - History of Political Thought 17 (1):36-59.
Stasis, or the Greek invention of politics.M. Berent - 1998 - History of Political Thought 19 (3):331-362.
Aristotle's Political Philosophy.David Keyt - 2018 - In Sean D. Kirkland & Eric Sanday, A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. pp. 393–412.
About the Impossibility of Absolute State Sovereignty: The Early Years.Jorge Emilio Núñez - 2014 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 27 (4):645-664.
Sovereignty as Autonomy.Raf Geenens - 2017 - Law and Philosophy 36 (5):495-524.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-01

Downloads
51 (#447,550)

6 months
14 (#181,413)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

“¿Es la "demokratía" semejante a la democracia? Lecturas contemporáneas de la democracia ateniense.Laura Sancho Rocher - 2018 - Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 51:15-33.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Stasis, or the Greek invention of politics.M. Berent - 1998 - History of Political Thought 19 (3):331-362.
Aristotle and the Origins of Natural Rights.Fred D. Miller Jr - 1996 - Review of Metaphysics 49 (4):873-907.
Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law.Colin Strang - 1955 - Philosophical Quarterly 5 (20):282-283.

Add more references