Frankena and Hume on Points of View

The Monist 64 (3):342-358 (1981)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Frankena sees moral point of view theories as steering a middle course between scepticism or relativism in ethics and absolutism or dogmatism. The constraints of a distinctive point of view limit the range of moral judgments, provide some basis to expect agreement between different moral judges, and generate standards if not of moral truth at least of moral acceptability. Since however these constraints arise only from the moral point of view, they are avoidable if the point of view is avoidable, and do not impose absolute inescapable demands on every person. Frankena sees the judgments made from the moral point of view to include categorical ones, but since he does not characterize the point of view itself as either the final court of practical reason or as an inevitable point of view, the categorical judgments made from that point of view are themselves externally conditional on taking that view-point. The most that can be said is that when and if one takes that viewpoint, certain demands are inescapable and unconditional. The whole illocutionary act of making the categorical moral judgment is as it were limited by the condition that one’s hearers, including oneself as hearer, share the point of view. Made fully explicit, what I am calling the external conditional would take this form: “Provided that one takes the moral point of view, one must acknowledge the unconditional obligation to …”. This is quite different from claims like “If one is a parent one has obligations to one’s child,” which is itself presumably a claim which may have an implicit initial qualifier of the form “From the moral point of view …” or “From the legal point of view …”. It might of course also be saying “From the point of view of practical rationality as such, a point of view which one cannot refuse to take, and beyond which lies no more comprehensive or corrected point of view …”. Frankena distinguishes this ultimately authoritative practical judgment from a moral judgment, while nevertheless suggesting that practical reason will normally endorse what morality has decreed. It is not, however, part of the very meaning of “moral point of view” that that point be final or inescapable for human persons.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,302

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Points of View and Practical Reasoning.Robert Brandom - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (2):321 - 333.
Evaluating from a point of view.James Rachels - 1972 - Journal of Value Inquiry 6 (2):144-157.
Morality and the View from Here.Wolf Susan - 1999 - The Journal of Ethics 3 (3):203-223.
A Confusion about ‘Moral’.J. H. Pillote - 1970 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 19:214-219.
The Common Point of View in Hume’s Ethics.Rachel Cohon - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):827-850.
System relativism.Charles Sayward - 1988 - Ratio 1 (2):163-175.
In Defence of Morality: A Response to a Moral Error Theory.Paul Barry - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (1):63-85.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-02-21

Downloads
57 (#393,182)

6 months
9 (#328,796)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Annette Claire Baier
Last affiliation: University of Otago

Citations of this work

El deseo más allá de la simpatía.Diana Zuluaga - 2006 - Ideas Y Valores 55 (132):31-52.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references